History of Universities
VOLUME XXVIII/2
2015
1
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere:
Reading Sacrobosco in the Renaissance
Richard J. Oosterhoff 1
Introduction
If you studied at university or grammar school in the sixteenth century,
chances are you read the Sphere by John of Sacrobosco, the most popular
introduction to the basics of astronomy since the thirteenth century.2
Perhaps you owned one of the hundreds of cheap quartos of the book
printed between the fifteenth and seventeenth centuries.3 Or maybe you
borrowed a copy from your college library, possibly one of the large folio
editions that included the commentaries of medieval scholastic doctors
like Robert Grosseteste or Pierre d’Ailly, alongside the orations and
additions of moderns teaching at the universities of Padua or Paris.
Perhaps you bought yourself a large volume, and instead of wasting
space in your commonplace book you filled the margins of your text
with observations and definitions, flagging contentious arguments raised
by your professor in his mathematics lectures. In preparation for disputations you underlined and repeated keywords in the text, to review quickly
as you moved on to more advanced treatises such as the Theorics of the
Planetary Motions. However you read it, the Sphere summed up your
knowledge of the cosmos.
The Sphere has received only passing attention from historians because
it was so basic. The first book surveyed the qualities of a sphere, and how
the universe was composed of nested spheres, with the four elements of
the earth at the centre. The second listed the various circles used by
astronomers to delineate parts of the sphere, such as the zodiac, and the
five zones of the earthly sphere. In the third book, the student would find
a basic account of how the signs of the zodiac moved through the night
sky, what this meant for days, seasons, and the various climates of the
earth, from the inhospitably cold north to below the equator, which ‘since
2
History of Universities
living conditions are bad, is not reckoned as a clime’.4 The fourth and last
book provided a rough description of the sun’s motion, with just enough
theory of general planetary motion to explain eclipses.
The Sphere hardly represents bold and exciting science, even by the
standards of the time. Yet its pages and the traces of its readers reveal
something we miss when we focus on extraordinary works and outstanding readers such as Copernicus, Jean Bodin, or Galileo.5 Indeed, as
Mordechai Feingold argued for the English universities and recently
William Sherman for English literature, our perspective on exceptional
works and thinkers risks distortion if we cannot set them against a
background of ‘ordinary’ textbooks and their readers.6 While examining
the mathematical textbooks of Jacques Lefèvre d’Étaples and his Paris
circle of students, I searched for such a backdrop against which to measure
these works and their uses; finding none, I began to compare all the copies
of such textbooks that I could find, especially the Sphere. My goal is offer
such a backdrop by giving a birds-eye view of the marginalia found in
hundreds of copies and dozens of editions of Sacrobosco’s Sphere.7 Following the example of William Sherman in tracing mostly anonymous
readers, pursuing Robert Darnton’s history of books ‘from below’, this
article is primarily an effort to map the ways that the ‘everyman’ reader of
Sacrobosco encountered the book.8
Before turning to annotations, however, in the first part of the article it
is necessary to survey the contents of the Sphere, its uses, and how it
transformed during the period as a site for innovation in commentary and
visual presentation. Then, in the second part, I situate Sacrobosco within
the university classroom by considering two readers we know something
about, Beatus Rhenanus at Paris and Henricus Glareanus at Cologne. The
majority of readers, of course, we know very little about, so in the third
part I consider Beatus’ and Glareanus’ annotations in comparison with my
broader collection of largely anonymous annotations. In this third part,
I offer a preliminary sketch9 for a history of Sacrobosco’s renaissance
readership—a readership chiefly of university students and masters, given
the Sphere’s longstanding place in the university cursus. In contrast to
studies of reading that focus on individuals, I have tried to give a baseline
for how this textbook was used; necessarily, my results are somewhat
impressionistic (though perhaps not so impressionistic as they would be
if focused on one reader). Yet annotations witness to the possibly glacial
and certainly profound ways that textbooks changed a discipline, at a time
when print catalyzed innovation in such textbooks. For heuristic reasons,
therefore, I have organized these marginalia into three categories. First,
I begin with Sacrobosco as most students encountered him, as an entry to
basic astronomical terms, examining how readers used various marking
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
3
strategies to integrate Sacrobosco into early modern letters, defined broadly
as philosophical, historical, and literary education. Second, I consider
marginalia that reflect the practice of comparing authorities, so powerfully
deployed by Renaissance intellectuals. Third, I address the specifically
mathematical literacy such marginalia reveal. Deploying the swelling commentaries and visual apparatus of new print editions, readers of Sacrobosco
more firmly embedded the Sphere’s cosmology into renaissance learning
even as they linked the Sphere with newer disciplines such as cosmography.
In the process, I suggest, such apparatus discouraged high-level mathematical creativity, but also encouraged some readers to attend more to
calculation.
The Expansion of Astronomical
Textbooks
If any work counts as a textbook, it is Sacrobosco’s Sphere, the longestlived mathematical set text of Western European universities other than
Euclid’s Elements.10 Yet the Sphere was by no means a stable object, and
especially in print it often served as the skeleton on which to hang many
different clothes. While the first printed editions of Sacrobosco’s Sphere
(1472) amounted to a few gatherings bare of images or commentary, by
the 1570s the talented Jesuit mathematician Christoph Clavius used the
Sphere as the frame on which to hang 500 pages of the most sophisticated
astronomy of the period.11 So far, historians have roughly divided the
book’s printed history into three phases. In the first, the book evolved a
growing apparatus of images and commentary.12 The second phase begins
in the 1530s, when quarto and folio editions especially published in
Venice and Paris gave way to small, inexpensive octavos first published
in Wittenberg, usually with Philip Melanchthon’s oration on astronomy
as preface.13 In this second phase, Sacrobosco also became the model for a
growing genre of textbooks, often under the name ‘cosmography’.14 In the
final phase, in the second half of the sixteenth century, we find long, thick
new textbooks roughly based on the Sphere, such as that by Clavius or the
Epitome astronomiae of Michael Maestlin (Heidelberg, 1582).15 In this
section, I try to analyze the rapid expansion of the Sphere during the earlier
part of its printed life, and consider what this implies about how readers
used the text.
The early decades of Sacrobosco in print illustrate well the transition
from manuscript to print: in uncertain fits and starts. For example, while
most manuscripts include at least some images, the very first printed
4
History of Universities
editions of Sacrobosco left only spaces for figures, perhaps intending readers
to fill them in.16 It may be these earliest printers followed manuscript
copying practices, where the reader might commission or purchase a copy
and later add rubrics or figures. How manuscript collections of astronomical
works were organized also helps explain the growing collections of texts that
surrounded Sacrobosco between 1472 and 1531. In manuscript, the Sphere
of Sacrobosco is normally found in collections of astronomical texts.
A copyist would, whether for himself or for another, include several similar
items of interest in the same codex, most often grouping them together by
subject.
From these manuscripts the historian can infer the uses to which such
collections were put. Usually along with the Sphere, which provided
the first rudiments of Ptolemaic two-sphere astronomy, one would find the
Theoricae planetarum (sometimes attributed to Gerard of Cremona), the
more advanced textbook on the planetary motions. One might find also
an introduction to calculation and geometrical operations, and some
applications such as a handbook on casting a horoscope in order to
make judicial or medical astrological predictions. Or—perhaps most
common of all—the manuscript would be rounded off with a compotus
manual, used to determine the date of Easter.17 Another especially
important item was the Alphonsine Tables, used to develop astronomical
medieval calendaria as a kind of almanach for predicting planetary positions. Ptolemaic astronomy as practiced from antiquity to the Renaissance
was useful for determining the longitudes of the sun and other planets,
and so for measuring the periods of stars and planets. These tasks required
several texts. The Theoricae planetarum outlined the basic conceptual
issues at play in this calculation. Roughly, the problem was that the sun
(like other planets) does not rotate around the earth at a uniform rate.
To account for this non-uniform movement, the Theoricae followed
Ptolemy’s Almagest by modeling the sun’s movement on an eccentric
deferent, a circle whose centre is not the earth. Thus the true angular
motion of the sun had to be calculated by using a trigonometric function
that allowed for the difference between the radius of the deferent and the
radius of the zodiac (centred on earth). In the case of the other planets,
whose movement is even more irregular from the perspective of earth,
Ptolemy and the Theoricae employed further geometrical constructions:
the epicycle and the equant point. But the Theoricae gave a purely
qualitative description of the arrangement of the Ptolemaic orbs, and
thus was insufficient to actually calculate the locations of these planets.
To find those, an astronomer needed astronomical tables (ephimerides)
along with canons, or instructions for using those tables. It is not
uncommon to find manuscript codices of astronomical works such as
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
5
the Sphere or the Theoricae together with Canones and Tabulae, forming
a complete set of astronomer’s tools.
Printed editions of the Sphere did not immediately come with these
practical components, though these editions were usually printed in collections. For their first two decades in print, most incunabula astronomy
textbooks included three works: John of Sacrobosco’s Sphere; Regiomontanus’ Contra Cremonensem, which attacked the old thirteenth-century
Theoricae; and his teacher Georg Peurbach’s Theoricae novae planetarum,
written to correct and replace the older book of the same title. None
included the ephemerides necessary, however, to make calculations or to
construct nativities.18 Of course, one could purchase these separately; but
their absence from the first printed collections including the Sphere suggests
that these collections were primarily meant to impart a conceptual understanding of the heavens, not an operative one.19
Beginning in 1495 astronomical textbooks expanded rapidly, as did
textbooks of the arts course in general.20 For one thing, textbooks began to
include commentary. The first of two such commentaries was published at
Paris in 1495 by the arts master Jacques Lefèvre d’Étaples, and until the
1530s was perhaps the most frequently reprinted commentary in Paris and
Venice. In 1498, one of Lefèvre’s colleagues, Pedro Ciruelo, produced a
similar commentary, based on a set of questions by Pierre d’Ailly a century
earlier. Contemporary bindings show that sixteenth-century owners often
bought multiple commentaries and had them bound together in Sammelbände, reading Lefèvre’s and Ciruelo’s commentaries in parallel.21 Printers
quickly sensed a market for multiple commentaries in one volume. In
1499, the Venetian printer Simon Bevilaqua published a compendium of
commentaries on the Sphere, including Lefèvre’s alongside other popular
commentaries by Cecco Esculano and Francesco Capuano, as well as
Peurbach’s Theoricae and its own commentary by Capuano. From 1499
to the late sixteenth century, this genre of compendia on the Sphere
swelled, reaching a high point in 1531 when Lucantonio Giunti published
an edition in Venice that included no fewer than sixteen distinct texts,
including the Sphere, old and new Theorics, medieval and Renaissance
commentaries on them, and orations in praise of the quadrivium.
As Sacrobosco’s Sphere evolved, the genre of the Sphere diversified and
became more technically demanding.22 Two changes command special
attention. First, the Sphere diversified into a broader genre that took on
elements from Ptolemy’s newly available Cosmography, so merging with
one of the most distinctive disciplines of Renaissance practical mathematics. At the same time, second, new versions and indeed commentaries on
Sacrobosco’s Sphere began to mention, and sometimes explain, newer
technical questions in mapping and calculation.23
6
History of Universities
First, the genre of the introductions to spherical astronomy diversified.
Even before print, there had been a number of introductions that merited
the title ‘sphere’; Sacrobosco’s work became the most popular introduction, and so defined the genre.24 But in the early sixteenth century, new
introductions to the Sphere began to incorporate map-making or cosmography as one of the main aims of the genre. Such works followed the
example of Ptolemy’s Geography—or, Cosmography, as it was more commonly translated at first—which had been newly discovered in the early
fifteenth century.25 Notably, Ptolemy’s approach to map-making offered
mathematical and astronomical techniques for projecting a cartographic
grid—he determined the longitudes and latitudes of places on earth from
their positions relative to the night sky. That is, Ptolemy focused on the
mathematical link between the cosmic sphere and the earthly sphere. In
this vein, new introductions to the sphere included the Cosmographiae
introductio of Martin Waldseemüller (1507), and Peter Apian’s Cosmographicus liber (1524).26 For example, in Paris Jean Fernel and Oronce
Fine each produced comparable textbooks through the presses of Simon
Colines, even as Fine helped Colines publish the Sphere commentary of
Lefèvre d’Étaples.27 Until 1528, when he gave up his affair with mathematics to become a respectable physician, Fernel was absorbed in the
world of mathematical instruments, and in his Monalosphaerium (1526)
and Cosmotheoria (1528) he reworked the subject of the Sphere with much
greater attention to the geometry and instruments needed to map the
heavens.28 Similarly, Oronce Fine successfully bid for a position as lecteur
royal in Francis I’s new Collège Royal with his compendium Protomathesis
(1532), of which the third part was a Cosmographia—Colines later republished it separately as De mundi sphaera, sive cosmographia (1542). Introductions to the Sphere often merged with the genre of geography, resulting
in a new range of astronomical texts.
The second major change in astronomical textbooks was that, even as
the genre on the sphere diversified, commentaries also became much more
technically sophisticated than Sacrobosco’s text itself. Like Sacrobosco’s,
all the treatises began with definitions of points and spheres from geometry, then moved to the structure of the heavens, and finally described
relationships between heavens and the habitable parts of the earth. Unlike
Sacrobosco, new authors transgressed the old theoretical bounds of the
Sphere, entering into practical concerns. They were interested in instruments and calculation, in applying mathematics to the world, often with
an eye to the art of mapping. While I know of one medieval commentator
who mentioned an instrument in the context of Sacrobosco’s Sphere,29 the
majority simply tried to transmit a qualitative understanding of the
cosmos to students, without meaning to make the student a practitioner.
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
7
In the early sixteenth century, textbooks increasingly aimed to teach
students how to manipulate the tools of the astronomer. By 1490, some
Venice editions were including a short introduction to geometrical terms
needed for doing astronomy: curves, right and acute angles, sections of
circles, and parts of spheres such as poles.30 In Paris, Lefèvre’s Textus de
Sphaera (1495) framed Sacrobosco within a short primer on sexagesimal
arithmetic, tables for calculating the rising and setting time of the sun and
planets, and accounts of the locations of cities.31 These new elements may
be related to new treatises on spherical geometry available from Greek
antiquity, such as pseudo-Proclus.32 Humanists frequently mentioned
such newer texts in their commentaries on Sacrobosco. So did Melanchthon did in his introduction to the Wittemberg edition, and the editor
(probably Oronce Fine) who added the marginal notes to editions of
Lefèvre’s Textus de Sphaera printed from 1521 onward, supplying Greek
references and renvois to the technical literature of antiquity.
These printed astronomical texts, especially when seen against the
backdrop of medieval manuscript collections of astronomical writings,
raise further questions of use. The more sophisticated introductions to
Ptolemy’s masterwork, the Almagest, found a strictly limited audience.
Regiomontanus’ Epytoma in Almagestum Ptolemei (Venice, 1496), famously the primary source of Nicolaus Copernicus’ knowledge about Ptolemy, was never reprinted.33 Early on, therefore, the kinds of resources a
reader needed to calculate the locations of stars, to compare maps, and to
test authorities, were not widely available. Meanwhile, it would have been
quite difficult to apply the astronomical knowledge presented in the
simpler Sphere and Theorica, for they included no tables for actually
transferring knowledge about the heavenly bodies from the page to
prediction. As Lefèvre noted in his own treatment of the Theoricae
(Paris, 1503), one wishing to actually ascertain or predict the positions
of the bodies should go elsewhere—to Ptolemy himself.34 In Lefèvre’s
view, the limitations of such textbooks to mostly theoretical inquiry was
not a particular problem. While he did not forbid the reader astrology,
Lefèvre tinged his description of such practical astronomy with prejudice
against the prognostications of the heathen, who understood but misapplied the knowledge of the heavens. His student-cum-colleague Josse
Clichtove, who faithfully commented on Lefèvre’s short treatise in
exhaustive (and sometimes exhausting) detail, reiterated the point in
1517. The astronomy of Sacrobosco and the Theorica tradition, he told
readers, should be for contemplation and not for prognostication.35 This
pedagogical ambivalence toward astronomy raises questions for historians.
For what ends did early modern astronomy students turn to Sacrobosco?
Did they simply turn to the night sky, in awe of the first mover as they
8
History of Universities
used their imaginations to apply the circles of their pages to the spheres in
the skies? Or was this awe meant to be inculcated only in the pages of
books, within the shadows of college yards and libraries?
The Sphere in the Classroom: Beatus Rhenanus
and Henricus Glareanus
Let us enter the Renaissance classroom through the experiences of the
Alsatian humanist Beatus Rhenanus (1485–1547) and the Swiss polymath
Henricus Glareanus (1488–1563). Both were exceptional readers in the
sense that they ended their lives as well-published authors and internationally regarded humanists, members of the close circle of humanists Erasmus
cultivated along the Rhine after his arrival in Basel in 1514.36 But from
the perspective of the history of science, they can serve as a kind of
‘everyman’ insofar as they embodied the ideal of encyclopedic erudition
that became the ideal of education in early modern Europe.37 While
diligent students, in other words, they can hardly be called astronomers,
even though Glareanus was known for skill in other mathematical disciplines such as cosmography and music theory.
Beatus Rhenanus came to Paris in the summer of 1503 to study with
Lefèvre d’Étaples at the Collège du Cardinal Lemoine. Since the early
1490s, Lefèvre had been renovating the range of university textbooks,
including new introductions to and commentaries on the standard mathematical works of the quadrivium as well as the philosophical works of
Aristotle: logic and natural philosophy, followed in later years by moral
philosophy and metaphysics. By the time Beatus came to Paris, a student
at Cardinal Lemoine could study the whole arts course using nothing but
the exciting new ‘cursus Fabri’. On arrival in 1503, Beatus bought many
books, but the only ones closely annotated with study and lecture notes
are the editions produced by Lefèvre and his other teachers.38 Given the
low interest in mathematics in fifteenth-century University of Paris, it is
striking that Beatus’ first year at Paris included three works on mathematics, alongside Lefèvre’s edition and commentary on the texts of Porphyry
and Aristotle’s logical Organon, and a second volume of Lefèvre’s paraphrase of Aristotle’s various works on natural philosophy. In his prefaces,
Lefèvre argued that mathematics should be restored to its old place in
the University of Paris, implying that study of Sacrobosco and geometry
had become a dead letter of the university statutes. At Paris, it appears that
the distinctive academic culture of each residential college determined
what and how students actually read. The cursus for the arts course leading
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
9
to the bachelor degree was not set by university statute.39 Even the
requirements for incepting MAs stated only the vague requirement that
the candidates have heard ‘at least one hundred lectures on mathematical
topics’.40 (An official recorded the usual interpretation: ‘this is interpreted
by the Faculty [of Arts] thus: that it is enough to have heard one book of
mathematics, such as the treatise on the sphere, and to be in the process of
hearing another book with the intention of hearing it until the end,
without lying’.41) Mathematics indeed kept a low profile in the statutes
of the medieval University of Paris. Beatus’ purchases suggest that, at least
at the Collège du Cardinal Lemoine, the story was different. In Lefèvre’s
own classroom, mathematics were of primary importance, studied early in
the BA—primary, in the senses of being basic, but also fundamental to
later disciplines.
As a student, Beatus read an edition with Lefèvre’s commentary published in Paris in 1500, though he later purchased two more copies. In
1504 he acquired an edition with commentary by Pedro Ciruelo and the
older quaestiones of Pierre d’Ailly. In 1505, he bought one of the Venice
editions that included several further commentaries, perhaps to supplement his own lecturing as an incepting Master of Arts. A fastidious notetaker and a compulsive book-buyer, Beatus put his ex libris on the title
pages of all his purchases, or on the first title page, when he bought several
books in a single Sammelband. This is the case with Beatus’ Sacrobosco: it
is bound at the end of a volume of three works, following some compendious introductions to practical and theoretical arithmetic and geometry
by Lefèvre, Josse Clichtove, and Charles de Bovelles, and then Lefèvre’s
advanced editions of number and music theory.42 Beatus therefore likely
read his Sacrobosco in the context of his study of natural philosophy and
logic, and probably after having studied some elementary arithmetic and
geometry (the more advanced treatises on number theory and music
theory are mostly free of annotations).
Henricus Glareanus most likely read and annotated his Sacrobosco
while in Cologne, a northern centre of education and textbook printing
with prestige second only to Paris.43 A native of the Swiss town Glarus,
Glareanus arrived at the University of Cologne in 1507 after attending the
grammar school at Rottweil in Württemburg, earning the BA in 1509,
and the MA in 1510. As at Paris, the masters directed studies as well as
living arrangements in each residential college or bursa; Glareanus first
studied at the Bursa Montis and then taught there as a master. For
bachelors, university statutes at Cologne were little clearer than those at
Paris, and mentioned nothing of mathematics. The statutes specified
mathematical requirements for masters more carefully: bachelors who
hoped to incept as masters should have spent two months in lectures on
10
History of Universities
the Sphere, as well as ten weeks on parts of Euclid, the Theorica, and
perhaps some of John Pecham’s textbook on optics, the Perspectiva communis.44 Perhaps the most remarkable implication of these statutes is that
students were not expected to have read Sacrobosco until they had already
earned the BA.
Glareanus’ Sacrobosco makes it plausible that he read the Sphere most
intensively during his preparation for the MA. His working copy is a
plain quarto edition printed in Paris in 1493.45 It is bound with another
copy of the Sphere, in the edition of Santritter (Venice, 1488), which
includes the oration of Regiomontanus and Peuerbach’s Theorica—Iain
Fenlon and Inga Mai Groote report that this copy, however, has fewer
annotations, mostly focused on the Theorica.46 Glareanus did not annotate his working copy, however, until at least 1507; near the end of the
book, he nuanced Sacrobosco’s account of the torrid climes by reporting
the experience of Amerigo Vespucci ‘in the Cosmographia’.47 The relevant letter of Vespucci had been published in 1507 with the Cosmographiae introductio that accompanied Martin Waldseemüller’s map
introducing the New World as ‘America’.48 Therefore Glareanus annotated this copy of the Sphere after April 23 1507, when the Cosmographiae introductio was published—that is, only after gaining the degree of
bachelor.
Beatus and Glareanus’ copies of Sacrobosco add to our growing picture
of the renaissance classroom. As printed books became more and more
common in classrooms, students sometimes copied into the margin the
detailed commentary of their teacher, keyed to particular words or
arguments—in rare cases, we can compare several identical sets of student
notes, providing us several views on the same classroom.49 Though
printed books were more widely used in classrooms, the ancient practice
of taking notes from dictation (the medieval term reportatio declined in
use) continued throughout the early modern period.50 Without multiple
copies from the same classroom, it can be difficult to prove when this
occurred, but large blocks of annotations found in some books give clues
to their source in class discussions.51 Beatus authenticated his schoolbooks
with the phrase ‘manu propria’,52 and then inserted large blocks of text
into the margins. In the process, when the lecturer spoke too quickly or
gave a name not yet familiar, Beatus sometimes left spaces that he
apparently meant to fill in later.
Figure 1. Lefèvre, Textus de sphera (Paris, 1500), BHS K1046a, a1v, detail.
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
11
In this list of ‘modern astronomers’, the name ‘Johannes de’ precedes a
blank, followed by the name ‘Georgius Purbachius’: Beatus had missed
the name ‘Regiomontanus’ in the lecture.
Beatus’ Sacrobosco reflects the experience of a university student fresh
from grammar school. Glareanus’ book instead was likely intended as a
reference for students, who might copy his notes into their own copies of
Sacrobosco. Recent studies of Glareanus’ later teaching notes suggest that
when he taught in the bursae at Basel, Paris, and Freiburg, he shared his
library and expected students to read the notes that filled his books. Some
of his notes resurface in students’ books, copying the thickly penned
capitals of headings and the smaller cursive of longer notes, and in some
cases even copying the notes word for word.53 Glareanus regularly
addresses his notes to readers. Years later, in another similarly markedup textbook, he explained the reason for his annotations: ‘Glarean to the
reader: What we have written here by our own hand, dear reader, you
should ponder again and again, and it should be imprinted on your
memory. You will find that this is very profitable for you, and it will
serve you as a sort of open door to the rest of the material in this
book’.54 In his notes on Sacrobosco, Glareanus sometimes likewise
addressed his reader directly. ‘But the reader will remember that you
call “uninhabitable” a zone which can hardly be lived in, so the poets
affirmed the truth [i.e. when Virgil and Ovid delineated the torrid
zone]’.55 Perhaps as early as his years at Cologne, Glareanus intended
that others use his own library.
We should imagine Beatus and Glareanus in a context of pedagogical
experimentation. Students wrote their annotations in the margins of new
printed textbooks. Sometimes, as Beatus’ marginalia show, this was done
in class—perhaps with the equivalent of a blackboard, so the master could
share details. Glareanus’ notes show that some lecture notes, however,
could be copied by students out of their master’s copy. This pedagogical
space frames the context in which the growing population of university
scholars read Sacrobosco.56
But what did studying astronomy look like, for most of these readers?
Before considering this question in more detail, a caution is in order.
Glareanus and Beatus had distinctive experiences, which only offer a
limited picture of Sacrobosco’s readership. Beatus’ habits as an unusually
punctilious reader served him well as editor of ancient works and a
corrector in Amerbach’s print shop.57 At Paris, Basel, and Freiburg,
Glareanus became a popular teacher, known for his sense of humour as
well as his talent for clear exposition—evident in the notes he shared with
students. Furthermore, they represent a distinctively northern education
only in the early part of the century. By the late 1560s at Wittenberg, the
12
History of Universities
Sphere was available in smaller octavos, and we have lecture notes that
survive in notebooks, independently from textbooks.58 And at universities
famous for medicine such as Bologna and Padua, where astronomy was
important because of astrology’s place in medicine, professors of mathematics were hired in a way that did not happen in the north until Oronce
Fine became royal professor of mathematics in 1531.59 With teachers
dedicated to mathematics, Italian universities could set schedules for these
disciplines that were more or less standard across the university—rather
than peculiar to individual colleges or bursae. Besides being limited as
representations of a northern experience, Beatus and Glareanus’ Sacrobosco are limited as part of a university readership. The marginalia in
Gabriel Harvey’s Sacrobosco, for example, reveal a kind of reading outside
the university, aimed instead towards courtly utility—a kind of reading to
be taken up at another time.60 Given these limitations, therefore, to gain a
broader perspective on how Sacrobosco was read in sixteenth-century
Europe, the experience of Beatus and Glareanus should be read in dialogue with the many anonymous annotations in copies of Sacrobosco
from the sixteenth century. On to the marginalia.
Kinds of Reading
We might wonder whether readers such as Beatus or the students of
Glareanus learned how to read in a way distinctively astronomical or
mathematical. Did Sacrobosco, in other words, foster what we might
call ‘mathematical literacy’? In order to see what is distinctively mathematical or astronomical in these marginalia, we must first consider the larger
context of reading habits shared by most readers of the time. For heuristic
purposes, I have found that student notes on the Sphere fall into three
broad categories of reading, which I now discuss in turn: (1) the mining of
astronomical knowledge for the sake of other literary texts; (2) critical
comparison of authorities on astronomical knowledge; and (3) calculations. The most distinctively mathematical forms of reading appear chiefly
in the latter two categories.
1. For the Sake of Letters
No doubt many early modern students held the two-sphere astronomy of
the Sphere in no more esteem than many secondary school students hold
calculus today: a technical hoop, to be avoided if possible. Yet the rationale
for reading Sacrobosco was evident. Sacrobosco was a useful component in
the cycle of arts that formed functional citizens of the Republic of
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
13
Letters—astronomy was to embed students more firmly in the language
and cosmos of the learned. Beatus’ annotations bring this motivation to
the fore. He carefully underscores several lines in Lefèvre’s letter prefacing
his commentary on the Sphere. There Lefèvre recalled how his Greek
tutor, the émigré George Hermonymus, convinced him to study mathematics. Beatus underlined a passage in which Hermonymus reported that
‘mathematics (if we believe Plato in book 7 of the Republic) not only is
useful for the republic of letters, but also has the greatest import for the
civil republic. Thus (Plato thinks) those who have the best natures should
especially be taught in mathematics’.61 Beatus observed in the margin that
it was George of Trebizond, the controversial Greek humanist, whom
Lefèvre and Hermonymus held up as a good example of such training. As
Beatus noted, the story shows ‘the not insignificant usefulness of mathematics’.62 Lefèvre and his circle of students and colleagues found in
mathematics a means for the reform of university education—indeed,
for the republic of letters as well as for civil rule.63
Such an education increasingly included technical subjects. Lefèvre’s
story, and Beatus’ marginalia, hints at the increasing profile of mathematics in literary life over the course of the sixteenth century, as education
became the point of entry into an expanding culture of civility. By the later
sixteenth century, polite acquaintance with the geometry of artillery or
navigation was hardly unusual in elite education. Such cultured appreciation of the arts depended on a tradition of books such as Sacrobosco’s,
books that integrated mathematics into a predominantly literary education.64 Indeed, genteel education sometimes mingled mathematics and
artisanal practice, for instance in turning spherical objects on a lathe; such
practices took their theoretical support from commentators like Lefèvre,
who first used the example of a lathe to show how a semicircle, when
turned around an axis, could produce a solid sphere.65 On his first
reading, Beatus passed by the passage. But he did not forget the lesson.
In a second copy of Sacrobosco that he bought in 1504, he corrected the
commentary of Pedro Ciruelo by saying that ‘This definition of the
sphere, given by Euclid, is rather a craftsmanlike fashion of making a
sphere, so it should rather be called a “description”’.66 Glareanus, when
commenting on the equivalent passage, gave the reason Euclid’s account
of a moving semi-circle could be called a definition: ‘Let one imagine that
this semicircle [i.e. the one Glareanus drew in the margin] be turned
around an an axis; which should be a sphere, as in the first causal
definition’.67 What Beatus thought of as an example of craft, Glareanus
thought of as a causal explanation. Beatus’ first Sacrobosco, by Lefèvre,
included the image of a lathe, which was reproduced in Paris through the
1530s, and then became standard fare in the editions of the Wittenberg
14
History of Universities
Figure 2. Opus novum astronomicum Jacobi Fabri Stapulensis, ed. Christianus
Sculpinus (Cologne, 1516), Newberry VAULT Ayer QB41 .S12 1508 no. 1, A4v.
The manuscript image most resembles those printed in Wittenberg editions after 1531.
printer Joseph Klug after 1532, as well as in editions that imitated him in
Paris and elsewhere. Some readers of other editions even copied images of
a lathe into the margins of textbooks lacking the figure: the ‘craftsmanlike’
analogy of the lathe became a topos in the genre.
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
15
Renaissance students like Beatus and Glareanus were taught to read
actively. They learned that ‘difficult words, or matters of speciall obseruation . . . should be marked out . . . with little lines vnder them, or aboue
them, or against such partes of the word wherin the difficulty lieth, or by
some prickes, or whatsoeuer letter or marke may best helpe to cal the
knowledge of the thing to remembrance’.68 Readers commonly learned
three tactics to mark up their books: manuscript titles for key sections;
short definitions and synonyms for words (sometimes scribbled between
the lines); and finally blocks of commentary on passages.69 So too in
mathematical books. Readers of Sacrobosco underlined, sketched manicules, and flagged key words or arguments interlinearly and in the margin.
They wrote out long scholia, sometimes from other books, sometimes
from lectures. And they also drew diagrams and other figures—as I will
discuss in the next two sections, this is perhaps one of the most distinctive
features of mathematical reading.
The bulk of notes in copies of Sacrobosco reflect the habits of reading
learned in grammar schools. In this mode, Beatus Rhenanus annotated the
ways his master’s commentary followed the standards of classical rhetoric,
jotting down the names of authorities from George of Trebizond to
Archimedes.70 In many cases, a little learning in astronomy was simply
another aid to understanding the literature of antiquity. What appeared to
be a distinctively astronomical form of reading numbers and tables turned
out to serve literary goals. The commentaries of Lefèvre especially encouraged this approach to the quadrivium, thickly supported as they were with
tables of the longitudes and latitudes of antique and modern cities.
(Lefèvre took advantage of the newly available Geographia of Ptolemy.)
On Sacrobosco’s account of the difference between ‘unequal’ days (measured by the sun, so variable in length throughout the year) and ‘artificial’
days (those measured by a clock, so always equal), Glareanus found the
opportunity first to explain how different parts of Europe counted their
hours either from sundown or sunrise, before expanding on how the
Gospel of Matthew counted from sunrise in Jesus’ parables.71 Other
readers of Sacrobosco frequently expected that their modicum of astronomical knowledge would serve other literary ends. In a copy now in the
Huntington Library, a reader copied out large sections of Cicero’s legal
oration In Rullam, drawing lines to link these quotations to cities that
Cicero mentioned such as Ligura, Capua, and Carthage.72 Sacrobosco, as
supplemented by these sixteenth-century editors and commentators,
thereby became a literary tool, providing a reader further details to place
the lives of ancient authors. Similarly, on the flyleaf of the copy now in the
Huntington Library, the reader quoted the newly available work of
Vitruvius, De architectura 9.2, comparing the ancient ‘Chaldean theory’
16
History of Universities
of Berosus on the moon’s phases with that of Aristarchus of Samos.73
(Berosus thought the moon comprised a light and dark hemisphere,
moved by the sun; Aristarchus argued that the moon circled the earth.)
The literary arrow could go the other way too, when literature clarified
astronomy. Much reading of astronomy, as of other early modern genres,
was soaked with proverbs and ancient bon mots, often added to the
titlepage as a kind of studious motivation. Beatus remarked that ‘the
intellect’s edge augments the power of sensible instruments’.74 Glareanus
contented himself with a line that summarized astronomy as a discipline:
‘Astronomy is the correct law and rule that looks to the magnitudes and
motions of the heavenly bodies above’.75 Sacrobosco himself had turned
to Ovid, Lucan, and Virgil to shed light on the workings of the heavens
and the character of the different climes.76 Readers frequently adorned the
titlepages with snippets of insight that sometimes stretched into fulsome
quotations. One reader of a Wittenberg Sphere from 1540 copied out on
the flyleaf ten lines from Ovid’s Metamorphoses on the subject of the
‘double motion’ of the heavens.77 Under the right conditions, letters not
only drove students to the text, but the poetic muse stirred within
astronomy itself. The same reader who turned to astronomy to enlighten
his reading of Cicero also penned his own lumbering lines in dactylic
hexameter on the ‘True Worship of God’, exploring the relationship
between humanity as the temple of God. To remind himself of the
meter, he added the first line of Virgil’s Aeneid, branded so deeply in
every schoolboy’s memory as the archetype of dactylic hexameter: ‘Arma
virumque cano, Troye qui primus ab oris’. He then professed his faith
with a hymn, in the same meter, on the structure of creation: ‘Amo deum
qui me creavit ex nihilo in mundo’.78
Astronomy and other mathematical works were read alongside logical
works. More systematic readers strategically noted the logical and rhetorical moves made by Sacrobosco’s commentators. In the late 1580s, an
otherwise unknown Nicholas Gavius reflected the common Renaissance
debates over rhetorical and logical order by noting the commentator’s
choice first to describe Archimedes as the inventor of spheres, before
naming Sacrobosco as the chosen authority of Parisian scholars. As he
pointed out, this is a matter of ‘quid est’ (the given topic or observation), which properly proceeds discussion of causes, ‘quia est’.79 This
particular reader, like many others, chose only to analyze the rhetorical
opening of the commentary. Some displayed much more stamina in
their commitment to parsing mathematical discourse according to the
standards of school logic: one of the three readers of Burndy 751765
(now at the Huntington) annotated and underlined hundreds of ‘major’
and ‘minor’ premises within Esculano, Capuano, Lefèvre, and d’Ailly.80
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
17
At first this suggests only the mundane observation that university logic
was everywhere, so that even in reading mathematical works the schools
encouraged a thoroughly unmathematical activity through endless detours
into rhetoric and dialectic—precisely what critics of the status quo such as
Henry Savile decried as the ruin of mathematical education.81 But at the
same time, when considered as part of the history of mathematics, such
dedication to logical analysis of astronomical reasoning is a reminder that
the shifts in rhetoric and logic that characterized Renaissance pedagogy had
implications for the quadrivium as well. This is not a minor point, since the
sixteenth century was a period in which the relative certainties of logic and
mathematical reasoning—not seen as the same thing—were in flux.82
Studying astronomy alongside other disciplines, readers often reflected
on the status of astronomy and its relationship to other domains of
knowledge. Glareanus especially commented on the difference between
poetic and astronomical kinds of truth. ‘Our author speaks according to
the opinion of poets, who call the torrid zone this [i.e. uninhabitable]’, he
observed.83 As Vespucci’s experience of travel all the way to the antarctic
proved, it was possible to live beyond the bounds of the torrid zone. But
Glareanus suggested that—unlike astronomers—poets could be allowed
some license: ‘you call “uninhabitable” a zone which can hardly be lived
in, so the poets affirmed the truth. For not many live below the torrid
zone’.84 By distinguishing poetic sententia from the precision of astronomers, Glareanus at once affirmed and limited the value of literature for
astronomy. The poets should be read in light of current experience, not
the other way around.85
Certain questions seem to have become a standard topos for delineating
astronomy from other domains. A popular question arose around Sacrobosco’s claim that the universe comprised nine spheres, the ninth sphere
having been introduced by astronomers to account for the precession of
the equinoxes. Philosophers noted the discrepancy with Aristotle, adding a
tenth sphere. Theologians sometimes identified this tenth sphere as the
empyrean, fixed in medieval astronomy on the authority of Peter Lombard’s Sentences.86 In fact, at least at Paris, it appears that the tenth sphere
had been a question of faith since the thirteenth century. Authorities such
as Bonaventure or Aquinas all supported the presence of the empyreum on
the strength of ‘probable arguments’ drawn from the Bible; some, such as
Pierre d’Ailly, tried out physical arguments as well, such as whether this
extreme, immobile heaven could influence lower spheres (though d’Ailly
did accept the empyreum).
Sixteenth-century students learned about the empyreum as a case in
navigating authorities. Beatus Rhenanus included a long paragraph on
the number of spheres, drawing on King Alphonse (of the Alphonsine
18
History of Universities
Tables, which turned the Spanish king into an authority), Peurbach,
Regiomontanus, and other recentes. ‘Beyond these heavens known by
nature [i.e. the seven planetary orbs and the stellar sphere], the sacred
theogians posit another heaven, the empyreum, which is fiery’.87 But
Beatus’ presentation of the theological argument is less than convincing,
and he gives most space to the physical argument against it noted by d’Ailly.
The theologians do not argue for the empyreum by naturally reasoning
about its properties, he reports, but on account of its spendour—and as it is
the seat of God, they insist it must be immobile. But that does not make
sense, according to Beatus, because if it were immobile, how would it
influence the lower spheres, which plainly do move? If the outermost
sphere were still, would it not slow inner spheres down? ‘But against this
others argue that the influence of this ruling sphere does not pertain to
the order of the bodily world, but only to the matter of this heaven, and
so it is known not by natural means but by divine contemplation’.88
The argument from faith considered, Beatus concludes with the arguments of astronomers and natural philosophers: ‘modern astrologers’, he
pointed out, ‘see that the fixed stars (the eighth sphere) has a three-fold
motion. Thus they conclude that two other spheres should be given
beyond the eighth sphere’.89
In a later note that returned to the topic, Beatus presented the problem
as unsolved and all options as open. He began by describing the differences between spheres, as properly solid objects, and orbs, as hollow
objects. ‘But these nine, properly called orbs, are commonly called
spheres’.90 Yet the number was not certain: ‘But the number, in this
matter, is undecided by philosophers, for according to some, there are
eight; according to others, nine, like this author [of the Sphere]; according
to yet others, ten’.91 The details here were not important. Instead, what
mattered was whether the Sphaera mundi was properly categorized. Beatus
defended the common terminology as an example of the species sometimes taking on the name of the higher genus it comes from, citing the
Topics I, and the examples of ‘dispositio’ (used to mean both ‘dispositus’
and ‘habitus’), and ‘casus’ (used to mean both ‘casus’ and ‘fortuna’), as
described in Physics II.92 In this case, rather than learning the distinctions
between how philosophers and theologians reasoned about the numbers
of spheres, Beatus ended the scholium with the encyclopedic question of
considering whether in fact the Sphere was about spheres. He (or his
master) reached the conclusion that it was, since the Sphaera mundi
dealt with the universe not as a sphere ‘taken simply, but rather by
aggregation’.93 This emphasis reveals Beatus less interested in astronomical arguments themselves as in checking a box on his chart of the
disciplines.
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
19
Readers often were concerned to set up the proper boundaries between
‘natural’ reasoning and the authority of theologians. One exemplar from
Cracow includes leaves of notes sewn in to the binding, which supplement
the dense marginal notations. Writing sometime after 1522, the student
describes three opinions on this question: that of the philosophers, who
claim only eight spheres; the astronomers’ view, who follow Ptolemy’s
account of nine spheres, including the seven planets, one in which the
stars are embedded, and a ninth to account for the slow procession of the
equinoxes; and finally the view of theologians, who posit a tenth sphere,
calling it the ‘caelum empireum’. The Cracovian reader cited Alphonse of
Spain among his sources, and followed a line of reasoning nowhere hinted
in the text before him by John of Glogovia (c.1445–1507). In particular,
he observed that one might wonder ‘beyond nature” (preter naturam)
about the source of the ninth sphere’s motion. Clearly not from the
spheres below, given Aristotle’s point that in heavenly motion, the larger
spheres possess greater motion and therefore must transmit it downward.
Thus the ultimate source of motion, he implied, must be from the fiery
residence of God, and the tenth sphere must exist.94 While deferring to
theologial authority, this reader, like Beatus, focused on the transmission
of motion between the orbs of planets to reason about their relations—but
with the opposite conclusion, that the motion of the lower spheres
suggests the existence of the empyreum.
Theological authority frequently motivated a reader’s marks. Remarks
often celebrated where the natural world reflected divine truth. Glareanus
pointed out that the centrality of the earth seems to be assumed by the
author of the Psalms: ‘David, the poet king: “Who laid the foundations of
the earth; it shall never be moved” [Ps 103:5]. In another place it says, “he
founded it upon the seas, and he set it on the waters” [Ps 24:2]’.95 Other
readers moved away from this devotional mode to polemics, expressing
outrage at offensive ideas. In most cases, however, they faulted the
commentators on the Sphere, not Sacrobosco himself. One of the readers
of the 1513 Cracow edition in Owen Gingerich’s collection crossed out
whole paragraphs. In one particularly emphatic act of effacement—doubly
crossed out—this reader evidently frowned on the impertinence of the
author, John of Glogovia, against the theologians who claimed that
Jerusalem is the center of the world.
John’s text showed that the claim made no sense, according to the
principles of the Sphere. Sacrobosco observed that if Jerusalem were at the
centre of the world, those living there would experience the unchanging
length of days (as at the equator), rather than a seasonal shift. But the
reader evidently was conconvinced, and found this inference impious
enough to deserve censure. Other traces of religious pressure are less
20
History of Universities
Figure 3. John of Glogovia, Introductorium compendiosum in tractatum spere
materialis (Cracow, 1513), private collection Gingerich, a8r. Beyond a censored
passage about Jerusalem’s location, this page bears annotations in two hands,
including examples of geometrical structures.
innocuous. Later in the sixteenth century readers defaced their books to
hide the confessional affiliations of their contents. It is common to find
exemplars of Sacrobosco with ‘Wittenburg’ scratched and scribbled out or
pasted over, along with the name ‘Melanchthon’. Melanchthon’s essay
prefacing the Sphere became an enormously popular exordium to mathematical study, and even colleges of Catholic religious flouted censorship
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
21
to include it.96 Censorship and efforts to evade censorship can be traced to
Protestants as well; in one copy in the Huntington Library, a reader has
carefully pasted over every single mention of Pierre d’Ailly, presumably for
his actions against the Hussites at the Council of Constance (1514–18).97
Yet censorship mostly extends only to names, not text itself. Such marks
suggest that in midst of confessional tensions, and despite the carefully
maintained disciplinary boundaries between theology and natural philosophy, some readers thought that knowledge of nature could be detached
from the lives of authors—nature as a source of non-confessional
knowledge—though they remained acutely aware of how their reading
could be perceived by religious authorities.98
The great majority of annotations on the Sphere represent ways of study
and reading deployed across the curriculum. Students considered the
rhetorical and logical peculiarities of the text before them, as well as of
its commentators, and as they did so, they integrated Sacrobosco into their
larger picture of the universe. This kind of reading did not necessarily
flatten out the differences between astronomy and other disciplines;
instead, students learned to recognize their contours, and to set them in
a hierarchy.
2. Comparison of Commentaries and Authorities
In the previous section, I surveyed a range of marking strategies that
readers of Sacrobosco might have applied to any sort of school text. This
section turns to a related practice that is important enough to deserve a
category of its own: the comparison of different texts, authorities, and
editions. Historians of science have begun to see how reading practices
could enrich technical works. Renaissance readers learned how to excerpt,
to recycle bits of information into commonplace books, to update their
books in the margin, and to compile such notes into reference works that
could then be again updated.99 For instance, in natural history the
discoveries of the New World entered the common knowledge of Europeans only slowly—these discoveries were absorbed into an intellectual
culture deeply committed to learned textual practices.100 Similarly, as with
the examples of lathe figures discussed above, the new printed textbooks of
astronomy standardized images and commentaries, and readers compared
diagrams and arguments across editions of Sacrobosco.
The expanding collections of commentaries and supporting texts also
made it possible to compare differing authorities within the volume. Not
all readers were as direct as Johannes Sebulerus [?] of Thuringia (otherwise
unknown), who delivered a verdict on the titlepage of his copy: he
denounced the fourteenth-century astrologer Cecco d’Ascoli as ‘dreaming
22
History of Universities
and raving’, while Capuano de Manfredonia was, he allowed, ‘a man of
excellent intellect’.101 I have already remarked how Peurbach was frequently mentioned by readers annotating discussions of the number of
spheres. Commentaries printed together, sometimes in parallel, introduced a kind of fluidity between books and editions, so that a reader
might work back and forth until the matter at hand was sufficiently
clear.102
Many annotations reveal the reader in mental dialogue with another
book. For example, in Pedro Ciruello’s commentary on the Sphere Beatus
Rhenanus pointed out where Ciruello echoed Lefèvre’s distinctive
argument—‘Lefèvre d’Étaples is of this view’.103 Such markings give a
sense for who populated the intellectual universe of the readers: not only
did Beatus note the names of typical astronomical authorities like Regiomontanus and Peurbach, but on the endpapers of the Sammelband and
several times in the margins he mentioned Dionysius the Areopagite, the
medieval Catalan Ramon Lull, and Nicholas of Cusa.104 Glareanus noted
various arguments from Ptolemy, with great respect, but accorded special
attention to Vespucci’s ‘Cosmographia’, and also alerted his students to
comparable passages in Gregor Reisch’s Margarita philosophica.105
Indeed, Sacrobosco allowed students to harmonize a broad intellectual
context—and many students were curious about astronomy’s links to
astrological or even magical power. Where Sacrobosco divided the sphere
of heaven into the various poles and circles, Lefèvre noted that ‘magicians
in particular identify four points’, and then listed them as the point of God
(east), of intelligences (midday), of the blind (west), and evil powers
(midnight).106 Beatus Rhenanus’ student notes took the question much
further. He announced the topic by listing ‘Prophetae, Magi, Philosophi’,
and then clarified their hierarchy: ‘Magicians are above philosophers,
being those who by skilful searching dig out the secret and hidden matters
of nature herself. Magic is the science by which one enters the mysteries of
nature. Our own Giovanni Pico della Mirandola in particular brought
light on this matter’.107 Thus astronomy offered tools for a Platonic
conception of universe filled with whispers of divinity. Using a table to
structure the four points and their ‘analogies’ (Figure 4), Beatus brought
the discussion to a close by bringing together Plato and the Bible. First he
noted that ‘the ideas of all perfect properties are in God’.108
Then he repeated the biblical quotation with which Lefèvre justified his
analogies: ‘for the invisible things of God, as the apostle says, are seen from
the creation of the world, understood through those things that have been
made’.109 Other readers found similar associations in Sacrobosco. Thomas
Corser, whose notes identify him as a late sixteenth-century presbyter,
while reading Lefèvre’s comments on the universe as machina mundi was
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
23
Figure 4. Lefèvre, Textus de sphaera (Paris, 1500), BHS K 1046c (Beatus’
Sacrobosco), a8r. Below the discussion of ‘Prophetae, Magi, Philosophi’, Beatus
includes a table correlating the four points of heaven to their analogies.
reminded of Cicero’s account of the world’s rational order.110 And then a
few pages later Thomas was reminded by Lefèvre’s comment on how
magicians organize the four points of the zodiac of a specific book on
natural magic, the Arbatel linked to Cornelius Agrippa.111
Since the Sphere was the most basic of textbooks, it is at first surprising
that readers of Sacrobosco also brought in scholarly, textual comparisons.
Such learned analysis seems overzealous; but Paris editions from 1520–38
as well as the increasingly popular versions from Wittenberg, complete with
Melanchthon’s preface, suggest that mathematics belonged to the wellrounded man of letters, because they included printed marginalia on Greek
phrases and references to Greek spherical geometry and newly available
authors like Proclus and Hesiod. A copy of a Wittenberg edition of the
Sphere, now at Houghton Library, exemplifies the kind of reading such
classical trappings could elicit. Probably in the 1540s, the reader noted that
Sacrobosco was working from the Campanus translation of Euclid’s Elements, and went on to verify Sacrobosco’s interpretation of Theodosius’
treatise on spherical geometry.112 Throughout the pages are short passages
from Aristotle in Greek, indicating the reader’s ability and desire to
24
History of Universities
integrate this medieval textbook with his classical authorities.113 While the
level of scholarship is low, it does indicate the company Sacrobosco was
expected to keep—successfully, such notes suggest, at least for a while.
Many, perhaps even most, annotations that compare Sacrobosco with
various authorities are not specifically mathematical. Like Glareanus’ use
of Vespucci to consider whether the sub-tropical zones are habitable, such
notes weigh the testimony of different authors; like the anonymous
marginalia identifying the longitudes and latitudes of cities Cicero had
mentioned, such notes put mathematics to work clarifying other texts, but
do not test the technical issue at play. But occasionally marginalia in
Sacrobosco reflect a distinctively mathematical form of reasoning, particularly in diagrams and figures.
The importance of diagrammatic thinking to astronomy is especially
obvious when readers seized on particular images and copied them into
their own books. Glareanus performed this service for his students in his own
Sacrobosco with particular care, most likely drawing on at least three other
editions of Sacrobosco. One image reproduces iconography found in the
many Venice editions, first illustrated by Erhardt Radtholt in 1485 and
quickly expanded upon by J.L. Santritter and H. de Sanctis from 1488.
From this iconography Glareanus took at least three elements: a cross-section
of the four elements within the aetherial spheres of heaven114 (Figure 5a); a
circle with an inscribed square and triangle to demonstrate that observations
of the heavens only harmonize with a spherical description of the earth’s
surface115 (Figure 5b); and a ship that bears two sailors, to support an
argument for the earth’s rotundity116 (Figure 5c; since only the higher sailor
can see a point on land, the earth must bulge to block the lower sailor’s view).
(a)
Figures 5a, 5b, 5c. Details from Joannes Sacrobosco, Tractatus de Sphera (Paris,
1493), Munich University Library 4 Inc. Lat. 310#6 (Glareanus’ Sacrobosco),
a2v, a3r, and a3v. Images from this Venice tradition of illustration are discussed
by Crowther and Barker, ‘Training the Intelligent Eye’.
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
(b)
(c)
Figure 5. Continued.
25
26
History of Universities
Further images clearly come from the other, sparcely illustrated, copy of
Sacrobosco in Glareanus’ possession: notably, a pair of diagrams of two
small people at different places on earth (Figures 6a and 6b). In the top
diagram, the different horizons for the two figures are neatly measured and
placed alongside each other, to show the different views of the heavens
available to observers at different longitudes on earth.
Similarly, in the second diagram, the two people are at different
latitudes; the one is ‘seeing stars’ (videns stellas) and the other ‘not seeing
stars’ (non videns stellas).
Glareanus reorients the illustrations to fit in the margins, but otherwise
copies them faithfully, down to the labels. His third source for illustrations
strays beyond the Sphere, but not far: Ringmann’s Cosmographiae introductio.
One of the several figures Glareanus borrowed from the book makes clear
that he had curated this collection of astronomical images for the sake of
students who might borrow his book. ‘Still, you see that, because of the
lack of space, not everything is worked out with the greatest of clarity. But,
dear reader, be satisfied enough with my work’ (Figure 7).117
Figure 6a. Sacrobosco, Opus sphericum (Cologne, 1505), C1r, detail.
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
27
Figure 6b. Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, A3v, detail.
Figure 7. Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, B6r, detail, copied from Ringmann, Cosmographiae introductio (St Die, 1507), a1v.
Given the care with which Glareanus copied such figures into his
1493 edition of Sacrobosco, he may very well have chosen to annotate
an older, uncommented, and unillustrated edition of the Sphere—by
1507 unusual—older edition of the Sphere specifically in order to create
a useful teaching textual and visual aid.
28
History of Universities
Figure 8. Lefèvre, Textus de sphaera (Paris, 1521), BnF res.v.209, a6r. To explain
the rotundity of heavens, the reader copied figures originally printed in earlier
Venetian editions of Sacrobosco.
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
29
Glareanus wrote his annotations as an example for others; his is perhaps a
specially consistent case of harvesting figures from a wider reading in order to
elucidate Sacrobosco’s text. But this was not an unusual practice. A reader
might link arguments throughout a text to a particularly helpful image,
referring back to the same image throughout the volume.118 More frequently,
readers drew on a stock of images that had become standard in the various
editions of the Sphere since the 1478 Venetian edition of Franciscus Renner,
and when a particular topos came up without the image, they supplied it out
of another edition. In particular, readers seemed to find compelling images of
the stars moving in a circle above observers on earth.119
These images show the astronomical reader wading through a flood of
book options, mixing and matching from different editions to find the
‘standard’ visual forms.120
As noted at the beginning of this section, historians of science have begun
to see learned practices of reading as an important way that natural knowledge was collected and taught. The new collections of competing commentaries on the text of the Sphere became a site for applying these textual
practices to astronomy. The result was that in the first decades of the
sixteenth century the medieval structure of the Sphere grew heavy under
thickening coats of antique paint. In many cases, these additional layers
cement Sacrobosco more firmly in traditional perspectives, as when Beatus’
evoked biblical motivations for the four astrological points of heaven; at the
same time, however, such accretions also bring the enormous apparatus of
two-sphere astronomy into dialogue with new sets of evidence, as when
Glareanus repeatedly mentioned Vespucci’s expeditions.
So too for figures. Cases like Glareanus’ Sacrobosco show how readers
encountered a specifically visual culture of astronomy. Not only did Sacrobosco’s readers learn to integrate their textual cosmos through Sacrobosco’s
words, but they learned to re-imagine the world visually by comparing and
collating a distinct visual grammar. Isabelle Pantin, Kathleen Crowther, and
Peter Barker have drawn attention to Kepler’s appropriation of figures from
the Sphere tradition in order to present Copernican astronomy in his
Epitome; expositors of the new astronomy depended on the Sphere’s visual
grammar in order to be understood.121 I would suggest that Sacrobosco’s
readers not only witness to the importance of physical means for visualizing
astronomical principles, but, as readers reproduce the most helpful figures,
one can see this visual grammar in formation.
3. Modes of Calculation
What did these new collections of textual and visual commentaries on
spherical astronomy mean for distinctively mathematical kinds of reading,
30
History of Universities
beyond visualizing themselves walking around spheres? Did they encourage
the reader to do more than simply repeat the qualitative doctrines of
astronomy or basic geometry? Since books supplied more tools for
calculation—tables and diagrams—students were confronted with the
expectation that they engage in mathematical exercises. Readers also had
other instruments and supplementary material available; one might imagine
the reader with a map or globe in front of him. In a copy in the British
Library, a reader doodled an image of a man holding up an armillary sphere
for examination, while a book lies open on a stand beside him—perhaps a
record of his own efforts to coordinate book and instrument.122
Many readers indeed performed calculations in the margins. The student
notes of Beatus Rhenanus show how this might look. Although the majority
of his annotations address qualitative questions, his opening notes also
include astronomical calculations. His copy of Sacrobosco included, as
many did, a short prefatory primer on geometrical shapes and—perhaps
more importantly—on how to do sexagesimal arithmetic. Beyond simply
working through the examples Lefèvre had provided, Beatus wrote down
three extended paragraphs to describe, step by step, how to add and subtract
degrees and minutes, and what to do with remainders.123 Several of Beatus’
notes go much further, reworking calculations that Lefèvre had done for his
students in the commentary itself, which presented tables of the distances of
the inner and outer surfaces of the orbs, their thicknesses, diameters, and
finally the circumferences of these shells.124 But whereas in the text Lefèvre
did not show the operations used to gain these numbers, Beatus redid
the calculations for each of the planets. For the circumference of the sun’s
orb, he wrote, ‘the convex surface of the sun [i.e. the outer surface of the
sun’s shell], doubled, gives 7,930,000 miles, which when multiplied by 22
is 174,460,000, divided by seven makes 24933851, and a remainder of one
tenth or one 9th’.125 Then, after similarly describing the dimensions of the
other planetary orbs, he continued with the most intriguing outcome,
concerning how many degrees are subetended by a portion of each planetary
orb: ‘the circumference of the sun’s heaven [i.e. its orb], which is 2,4[9]
33,857, divided by 360 makes 69,23[0] with 57 remaining, in which place
an integer is put in the book, that is 69,231’.126 Here one can see how a
degree grows in direct proportion to its distance from earth. Beatus simply
narrates the operation in this verbal format, which means that he must have
copied the results of long division or multiplication either from an abacus or
tablet, or perhaps from a master performing the calculation in the lecture—
small errors in the numbers, which do not affect the accuracy of the outcome,
show that these notes are a ‘clean copy’, copied from previous work.127
Beatus therefore learned specifically mathematical kinds of reading
practices through his study of Sacrobosco. The most important practice
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
31
is familiar to any historian working with mathematical sources: reworking
numbers on scratch paper. Redoing the work of Sacrobosco (or his commentator) gave Beatus the opportunity to see things he would have missed
otherwise. The activity cements the kinds of operations (relationship of
radius, circumference) involved in establishing basic dimensions of the
known universe—affirming trust in those astronomical numbers. The
activity of checking work allows Beatus to distance doing astronomy from
the book alone. In his own words, he distinguishes his own calculations
from what is ‘in the book’ (above). Further, doing the work himself also puts
Beatus in a position to critique the book; his results leave remainders, which
he observes have been smoothed into simple units in the book’s tables.
This is not to render Beatus a thwarted mathematician. Rather, he
exemplifies mathematical literacy developing within a humanistic context.
Beatus’ notes reveal him adopting these distinctively mathematical modes
of reading—mathematical literacy—within a context of erudition. There
is something of the philologist or grammarian’s urge to gloss every line
when Beatus writes a table for comparing units of measurement from the
inch (digitus) to the mile. After all, it is hard to believe he actually intended
to transmute the millions of miles between earth and the planets into
cubits, feet, or palm-breadths. But a short note besides Lefèvre’s account
of measurements shows why Beatus found this worthy of note within
astronomy. Astronomy measures the heavens and ‘in the same way that a
letter is the smallest part in grammar, and a word or locution is likewise the
smallest part in logic, so also the inch is the smallest part in the discipline
dealing with weight and measurements’.128 At the Collège du Cardinal
Lemoine, Beatus learned disciplines beginning with their principal, smallest
parts.129 Such encyclopedism, as several historians have shown, also motivated the grammarians, from Poliziano to Guillaume Budé, whose famous
treatise De asse et partibus (Paris, 1514) showed the fundamental importance
of understanding ancient coins, measurements, and their conversions for
calculating the chronologies and texts of antiquity.130 From this perspective, the future Beatus Rhenanus—the philologist so dear to Erasmus—is
still visible in a table of unit conversions.
Glareanus was another example of such erudition—he updated Budé in
his own Liber de asse et partibus eius (Basel, 1550)—but also hoped to
make his students not only careful readers, but mathematical readers. On
the same section of Sacrobosco that Beatus reworked, Glareanus also
helped his students calculate the dimensions of the universe. Like Beatus,
he added a small table for converting units from inches to feet to miles.
Then he addressed the problem of the earth’s circumference. Following
Eratosthenes, Sacrobosco suggests 252,000 stadia, which Glareanus
observed is based on the proportion of one heavenly degree to 700 stadia.
32
History of Universities
‘But, as [Gregor] Reisch says in the Philosophical Pearl, Ptolemy says that
one degree corresponds to 500 stadia. Multiplied by the 360 degrees of
heaven, these produce the number of 180,000 stadia’ for the earth’s
diameter.131 He went on to derive other basic values from 252,000 stadia
for the earth’s circumference, such as the earth’s diameter and radius.
The student who simply copied Glareanus’ notes would have missed
the distinctive mathematical skills Beatus learned by doing the calculations
himself. With the benefit of a calculator, it becomes obvious that Glareanus has made some short cuts. For example, to determine the ‘whole
earth according to its three dimensions’ he requires the multiplication of
the earth’s diameter (given as 80,181 stadia) by its circumference
(252,000). But the product he gives is 20,205,864,000, which is the
product of 80,182 stadia—because in fact he rounds a remainder down,
at one point, and rounds it up, at another, to simplify the calculation.
A student who missed this would have not learned to appreciate the ways
small errors can creep into large calculations.
If less committed to raw calculation than Beatus’ teacher, Glareanus
nevertheless took extraordinary care to help his students visualize mathematical underpinning of physical phenomena. This is not only evident in
the abundant diagrams he culled from various sources, but in his manuscript explanations themselves. He added a perspectival gloss to a section
where Sacrobosco addressed the apparent magnification of the moon near
the horizon, explaining it was caused by ‘certain vapors ris[ing] between
our sight and the sun . . . separating our visual rays’.132 To understand
this, Glareanus helped his reader through some geometry of perspective.
In the margin he reconstructed a diagram to explain how a light ray
refracted through different media bends. ‘The thing appears out of its
actual location. So let cd be the surface of the water that contains the
seen object b. Let there be a perpendicular bd erected, and an eye
existing in the air at o. A ray proceeds from the visibile object to the
eye [o], broken at point c by the perpendicular cf. By the 16th proposition of the Perspectiva, part 1, the ray continues to o; if the medium
were uniform, it would proceed to g. Therefore you will see a pyramid
between the object b and the perpendicular line bd joined at point l.
And the same eye o judges [b] to be B.133 So it is evident that the eye
sees o in the water through a refracted ray (the basis for this is the 15th
proposition of the Perspectiva, part 1). [ . . . ] Thus an eye in a rarer
medium sees an object in a denser medium as nearer and greater than it
actually is’.134 Twice Glareanus here cites the Perspectiva communis of
John Peckham—yet neither proposition cited offers the geometrical
argument of Glareanus, offering instead physical accounts of how denser
mediums cause greater resistance to light rays.135 Instead, Glareanus
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
33
Figure 9. Glareanus’ diagram of a light ray refracted in water in his copy of
Sacrobosco, A3r (detail at left) bears resemblance to one in an early printed
edition of John Peckham’s Perspectiva communis (Venice, 1504), 4r (detail from
Google Books at right). Note that I have added the ‘b’ where the figure has been
trimmed off in rebinding.
apparently gave his student his own geometrical reconstruction, extrapolating from one of the diagrams of a ray refracted in water (figure 9).
The student who copied this note would have encountered not a
qualitative account of the reasons for refraction (which he could find in
Peckham), but instead worked through a geometrical description, primarily in dialogue with a diagram. Specifically, the student must mentally
track the relations of lines and points while keeping their definitions in
view—a specifically geometrical form of reading.
Glareanus’ attention to diagrams as a teaching tool was exemplary, in
part because he recognized the limits of his medium. He repeatedly stated
that concepts hard to see in the descriptions or diagrams in this book
would be clearer with physical instruments. This was true for Sacrobosco’s
description of an instrument, where Glareanus said ‘you do not understand what he says here about the astrolabe; but you will see, for it is easy
to see this in [an actual] astrolabe’.136 But Glareanus also pointed out the
limitations of the two-dimensional diagrams he himself drew. The shape
of the zodiac zones passing around the earth ‘can be beautifully seen in a
spherical body, and is hard to picture on a flat surface’.137 The mind’s eye,
in imagining the heaven’s motions, was limited by the challenge to the
hand, in drawing on a plane. ‘I think the reader will find this the hardest to
draw’, he wrote of the ascensions of the zodiacal signs over the horizon.
‘For you will see this much more in a solid than in a plane. Therefore, so as
not to waste time uselessly, I passed over these things’.138 At some point,
pen and paper fail to explain all the motions of the heavens. At that point,
Glareanus uses his notes to gesture towards the world they are trying to
understand. The page marks its own limits.
34
History of Universities
Figure 10. Lefèvre, Textus de sphaera (Paris, 1527), Houghton f EC.Sa147s.1527,
title page.
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
35
And marginalia in other copies suggest that the experience of Beatus and
Glareanus was not isolated. An extreme example, showing the relationships
between the expanding genre of introductions to spherical astronomy, can
be found in one Houghton copy of Sacrobosco that is bound together with
Fernel’s Monalosphaerium and Cosmotheoria. Fernel’s books focused on the
geometrical and instrumental operations necessary to calculate days, distances, and planetary locations, but all three books in the volume are filled
with scribbles in three hands, of which one in particular shows an obsession
with calculation, filling margin after margin.139
As enthusiastic as this reader was, his mathematical skills were not
terribly sophisticated—most scribblings appear to be to calculate the
periods of planets to find planetary conjunctions—but nevertheless these
fervid sums indicate readers increasingly turning to quantification even in
introductory works.
Many readers did little more than label the diagrams already printed in
their Sacrobosco; others filled the diagrams in and decorated them with
flourishes.140 Among the most interesting, as like those already discussed
in this paper, are the horoscopes drawn in the margins of such textbooks—
particularly in volumes that contain Lefèvre’s commentary. Even though
Lefèvre and his students (such as Josse Clichtove) warned that they did
not teach astronomy primarily for prognostication, they offered examples
of how to locate planets and constellations. This was enough for some
readers, who analyzed horoscopes in the very margins of their copies.141
Quite possibly such horoscopes originated in collections of genitures
later published in the sixteenth century by erudite experts such as Girolamo Cardano or Luca Guarico.142 Certainly these markings reveal
readers integrating their basic textbooks with the growing field of technical
knowledge—interpreting the qualitative description of astronomical principles in Sacrobosco as well as reflecting on the quantitative information in
the charts of planetary positions. These traces remind us that, through the
practice of astrology, astronomy served physicians and court advisers
throughout Renaissance Europe—and as Sacrobosco’s apparatus grew
more technically sophisticated, so did its utility to prognosticators, whether
would-be professionals or curious do-it-yourselfers.
Such notes suggest that technical discussions in textbooks did, in fact,
make technicians. Together, Beatus and Glareanus exemplify a mathematical literacy often taken for granted in the history of mathematics, even
though this growing literacy links the new technical texts pouring from the
printing presses with the growing fascination with mathematical learning
in the sixteenth century.143 In particular, these erudite humanists-intraining exemplify the kind of basic skills needed to read the newlyfashionable cosmographies; both readers encountered Sacrobosco in
36
History of Universities
Figure 11. Compendium of the Textus sphaerae (Venice, 1508), Huntington,
Burndy 751765, 55v. Such a detailed horoscope would have required the aid of
other reference works, notably an ephemerides.
dialogue with either Ptolemy’s Cosmographia or Ringmann’s Cosmographiae introductio. I would suggest that by watching Beatus and Glareanus
learn and teach, we see mathematical literacy become an integral part of
erudite education—and that this included some distinctively mathematical forms of reading, such as reworking calculations, relating diagrams to
geometrical narratives, and indeed endeavouring to mentally reconstruct
three-dimensional movements from words and limited diagrams.
Conclusion
Reader marks from this long period suggest that as early modern textbooks
diversified in print, Sacrobosco was dressed up in ever richer layers of
images, commentary, and technical apparatus, and the book’s audience
grew more literate in the arts of quantification. The point is significant,
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
37
precisely because Sacrobosco was the most basic of introductions to
astronomy. If mastering Sacrobosco now required more than an intuitive
sense for geometry and also entailed some knowledge about the calculation of longitudes and latitudes, then the early sixteenth century is an
important locus in the shifting technical literacy of Europe—to wax
grandiloquent, a weighty moment in the history of the interface between
practice and theory. Readers working in margins witness to this shift.
It is beyond the scope of this article to claim whether the changes
described in the first part of the paper—the expanding collections of
commentaries and visual programs of Sacrobosco—in fact caused changes
in reading habits. A careful argument for this claim would investigate
annotations and marginalia in manuscripts, and more rigorously compare
earlier to later printed editions. But I can report that the most technically
sophisticated annotations are usually found the margins of books with
denser commentary and visual apparatus. Beatus’ notes show this well.
Glareanus’ Sacrobosco is unusual as an example of dense, technically
sophisticated annotations appearing in an edition devoid of images—but
Glareanus, as I have shown, depended on several visually sophisticated
editions of Sacrobosco in order to create his unique working copy. Based
on the evidence so far, I would contend, books with more technical
apparatus and tables were likely to foster greater technical literacy.
But this legacy is deeply ambiguous. Certainly such well-appointed
textbooks firmly ensconced the mathematical disciplines within the training of elites, even encouraging practical uses of that mathematics—at least
in some students. But their annotations rarely indicate a programme of
mathematical invention. For most, the regime seems to be one of memorizing rules, applying them, and moving on to the next topic. One need
not go so far as Lisa Jardine and Anthony Grafton in their celebrated
account of humanist education as docility-inducing drudgery to observe
that readers rarely found in Sacrobosco the spark of mathematical ingenuity or creativity.144 The controversial Gabriel Harvey mostly recorded
gossip about the ‘best’ mathematical authors and propaganda for the
practical significance of the subject, in his copy of Sacrobosco.145 Perhaps
Sacrobosco, as diverse a genre as the Sphere had become, remained the
wrong sort of book for deeper creativity.
At the same time, the fact that students were reading and doing more,
and more sophisticated, astronomy should not obscure the fact that the
cosmology Sacrobosco taught did not change. Earlier I described a copy of
Sacrobosco now at Houghton Library as an extreme example of how
readers increasingly tended to work out astronomy in calculation. As
part of its frontispiece is the phrase ‘Altius insurgit animus sub imaginem
mundi’ (The mind rises higher below the figure of the world).146 Ptolemy
38
History of Universities
and Sacrobosco might have subscribed to this ancient lofty goal for
astronomy, and certainly Lefèvre claimed that mathematics was primarily
important for his students because it would raise their souls to the
divine.147 When seen in the context of the other scribbles and scratches
that fill the margins of the volume, this phrase becomes an instructive
paradox. The high religious aims of natural inquiry were not an alternative
to or disconnected from the increasingly practical and technical applications of mathematical inquiry. Readers could hold these different aims
together. The broadest conclusion of this paper, then, is that early modern
astronomical books were integral to the growing emphasis on mathematical utility148—and yet, by incorporating the latest insights into an ancient
genre, they also fostered a profound conservativism that embedded the old
world picture deeply into early modern culture.
Reader marks make clear that Sacrobosco’s Sphere remained important
for a long time. I have concentrated on sixteenth-century readers—but
marginalia offer another insight into the length of time that Sacrobosco
served as an introduction to an understanding of the cosmos. While the
book was printed through the middle of the seventeenth century, the last
Elzevier edition of 1656 has been considered ‘anachronistic’.149 Perhaps.
But such a judgment does not account for the saturation of seventeenthcentury libraries with volumes that were already old and yet were read
afresh. The Houghton volume just mentioned bears on the titlepage
‘perlegitur Mart. 1, 1646/7’, and it is only one of a great many sixteenthcentury editions that bear the marks of seventeenth-century readers. If we
wish to understand why the geocentric world-picture captured the imaginations of most Europeans until well into the seventeenth century, understanding Sacrobosco’s readership is a good start.
Centre for Research in the Arts, Social Sciences and Humanities
Alison Richard Building
7 West Road
Cambridge CB3 9DT
References
1. I am grateful for the help of several modern readers of Sacrobosco: to Kate
Isard, for stimulating questions; to Owen Gingerich, for sharing his collection;
to Roger Gaskell, for sharing his vast knowledge and some images; to Alexander Marr, for responding to an early draft; to Kathleen Crowther and Peter
Barker, for the typescript of a paper just published in Isis; and as always to
Robert Goulding, for encouragement and close reading. The reviewers’ comments were of great help in revising the article, particularly those of Renée
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
39
Raphael, who generously gave up anonymity. The following abbreviations are
used in this article: BL ¼ British Library; BHS ¼ Bibliothèque humaniste de
Sélestat; BnF ¼ Bibliothèque nationale de France; Houghton ¼ Houghton
Library, Harvard; Huntington ¼ Huntington Library, Pasadena; Newberry ¼
Newberry Library, Chicago.
Sacrobosco is unknown except through his works, which include an Algorismus
(basic arithmetic), and Computus, as well as the Sphere. He possibly wrote a
treatise on the quadrant as well. Lynn Thorndike, who wrote the one extensive
study of Sacrobosco’s work, suggests he was active in the first decades of the
thirteenth century. Lynn Thorndike (ed. and trans.), The Sphere of Sacrobosco
and Its Commentators (Chicago, 1949), 5–6.
Jürgen Hamel, ‘Johannes Sacrobosco: Handbuch der Astronomie, Kommentierte Bibliographie der Drucke der ‘Sphaera’ 1472- bis 1656’, in Dietmar
Fürst, Dieter B. Herrmann, & Eckehard Rothenberg (eds), Wege der Erkenntnis: Festschrift für Dieter B. Herrmann zum 65. Geburtstag (Frankfurt am Main,
2004), 115–70.
Thorndike (ed.), The Sphere of Sacrobosco, 112. ‘quoniam prave est habitationis, sub climate non computatur’.
Paradigmatic studies of reading often consider only individual readers: Lisa
Jardine & Anthony Grafton, ‘Studied for Action’: How Gabriel Harvey Read
His Livy’, Past & Present 129 (1990), 30–78; Ann Blair, The Theater of Nature:
Jean Bodin and Renaissance Science (Princeton, 1997); William H. Sherman,
John Dee: The Politics of Reading and Writing in the English Renaissance
(Amherst, 1997); Nicholas Popper, Walter Ralegh's ‘History of the World’ and
the Historical Culture of the Late Renaissance (Chicago, 2012). The wonderful
study of astronomical marginalia by Owen Gingerich, An Annotated Census of
Copernicus’ De Revolutionibus (Nuremberg, 1542 and Basel, 1566) (Leiden,
2002), has set a high bar for studying marginalia; readers of De revolutionibus
can hardly be identified as a kind of ‘everyman’. William H. Sherman has put it,
‘generalizations about Renaissance marginalia are hard to come by . . . . But there
is a pressing need for information that will generate some larger patterns across a
wider range of books and readers’: ‘What Did Renaissance Readers Write in
Their Books?’ in Books and Readers in Early Modern England: Material Studies,
ed. Jennifer Andersen & Elizabeth Sauer (Philadelphia, 2001), 119–37.
Mordechai Feingold, The Mathematician’s Apprenticeship: Science, Universities
and Society in England, 1560–1640 (Cambridge, 1984), 16–22; William
H. Sherman, Used Books: Marking Readers in Renaissance England (University
Park, PA, 2009). On the importance of textbooks and universities for understanding science during this period, see Patricia Reif, ‘The Textbook Tradition
in Natural Philosophy, 1600–1650’, Journal of the History of Ideas 30 (1969),
17–32. On textbooks in this period, see Emidio Campi, Simone De Angelis,
& Anja-Silvia Goeing (eds.), Scholarly Knowledge: Textbooks in Early Modern
Europe (Geneva, 2008).
At least twenty per cent, I estimate, of the copies I have seen bear significant
marginalia, a figure comparable with Sherman’s study of several thousand
40
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
History of Universities
books across multiple genres (cit. note 6). The tendency of rare books buyers
until recently to value ‘clean’ exemplars suggests that more exemplars were
annotated in the sixteenth century than we now have.
Sherman, Used Books; Robert Darnton, ‘ “What Is the History of Books?”
Revisited’, Modern Intellectual History 4 (2007), 496. Ann Blair specificially
outlines ‘collective reading practices’ as an emerging research direction for the
history of science in ‘Scientific Readers: An Early Modernist’s Perspective’,
Isis 95 (2004), 420–30. See also, to a lesser degree, Blair’s study of reference
works and reading in Too Much to Know: Managing Scholarly Information
before the Modern Age (New Haven, 2010). Her more recent approach
complements the histoire totale of single readers found in the studies in
footnote 5.
Since there remain countless small textbooks in every collection of early
books, most unexamined, this article is necessarily a ‘preliminary sketch’
that must be filled in and corrected.
Anthony Grafton has pointed out the perplexing diversity of books that
count as textbooks—namely, books read for and in class—during this period,
in ‘Textbooks and the Disciplines’, in Scholarly Knowledge, 11–16. It appears
that Boethius’ works on arithmetic and music were replaced earlier than
Sacrobosco: Ann E. Moyer, ‘The Quadrivium and the Decline of Boethian
Influence’, in Noel H. Kaylor and Philip E. Phillips (eds.) A Companion to
Boethius in the Middle Ages (Leiden, 2012), 479–517.
Christoph Clavius, In Sphaeram Ioannis de Sacro Bosco commentarius (Rome,
1570). Later editions acquired over a hundred pages of further material. See
also Peter Barker, ‘The Reality of Peurbach’s Orbs: Cosmological Continuity
in Fifteenth and Sixteenth Century Astronomy’, in Patrick J. Boner (ed.),
Change and Continuity in Early Modern Cosmology (Berlin/New York, 2011),
7–32. An in-depth reading of Clavius’ astronomy is found in James Lattis,
Between Copernicus and Galileo: Christopher Clavius (Chicago, 1994).
The visual reorganization of the Sphere is addressed by Owen Gingerich,
‘Sacrobosco Illustrated’, in Lodi Nauta & Arie Johan Vanderjagt (eds),
Between Demonstration and Imagination: Essays in the History of Science and
Philosophy Presented to John D. North, (Leiden, 1999), 211–24; Isabelle
Pantin, ‘L’illustration des livres d’astronomie à la renaissance: l’évolution
d’une discipline à travers ses images’, in Fabrizio Meroi & Claudio Pogliano
(eds), Immagini per conoscere: Dal Rinascimento alla Rivoluzione scientifica
(Florence, 2001), 3–42; Jürgen Hamel, ‘Johannes de Sacroboscos Sphaera’,
in Stephan Füssel (ed.), Gutenberg-Jahrbuch, 81 (2006), 113–36. On the
visual strategies of Sacrobosco primers, see especially Kathleen M. Crowther
& Peter Barker, ‘Training the Intelligent Eye: Understanding Illustrations in
Early Modern Astronomy Texts’, Isis 104 (2013), 429–70. An analogous
argument can be found in Steven Vanden Broecke, ‘The Use of Visual Media
in Renaissance Cosmography: The Cosmography of Peter Apian and Gemma
Frisius’, Paedagogica Historica 36 (2000), 130–50.
F.R. Johnson, ‘Astronomical Textbooks in the Sixteenth Century’, in
E. Ashworth Underwood (ed.), Science, Medicine, and History: Essays on the
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
41
Evolution of Scientific Thought and Medical Practice Written in Honour of
Charles Singer (Oxford, 1953), i. 285–302. On the change from larger to
smaller formats, see Owen Gingerich, ‘Sacrobosco as a Textbook’, Journal for
the History of Astronomy 19 (1988), 269–73. The preface of the Wittenberg
editions is analyzed by Isabelle Pantin, ‘La lettre de Melanchthon à
S. Grynaeus: avatars d’une défense de l’astrologie’, in Divination et controverse
religieuse en France au XVIe siècle (Paris, 1987), 85–101.
Johnson, ‘Astronomical Textbooks’, 299–300.
Ibid., 300–1.
E.g. Tractatum de spera (Venice, [1472]), CUL Inc.4.B.3.8. Thanks to Roger
Gaskell for this example.
Examples of this sort that I have seen include: Houghton Library MS Typ 43;
Ambrosiana A 183 Inf.; Ambrosiana E 12 Sup.; Ambrosiana H 75 Sup.;
Ambrosiana I 90 Sup.; Ambrosiana M 28 Sup.; Ambrosiana M 35 Sup.;
Ambrosiana N 50 Sup.; Ambrosiana T 69 Sup. For descriptions of many
similar MSS, see Lynn Thorndike & Pearl Kibre (eds), A Catalogue of Incipits
of Mediaeval Scientific Writings in Latin (Cambridge, MA, 1937). A longer
examination of one such MS (BL MS Arundel 66) is Hilary M. Carey,
‘Henry VII’s Book of Astrology and the Tudor Renaissance’, Renaissance
Quarterly 65 (2012), 661–710. A rare account of how fifteenth-century
students may have used such manuscripts is James S. Byrne, ‘The Stars, the
Moon and the Shadowed Earth’ (PhD dissertation, Princeton, 2007), chap. 2.
On other works published with incunabula editions of Sacrobosco’s Sphere,
see Hamel, ‘Johannes de Sacroboscos Sphaera’.
These astronomical textbooks define, as much as instruments, the ‘context of
use’ for astronomical practice. Their study will enrich debates over whether
the ‘utility’ of astronomical models was primarily conceptual or operative.
The poles of current scholarship on this question are defined by Jim Bennett,
‘Knowing and Doing in the Sixteenth Century: What Were Instruments
For?’, The British Journal for the History of Science 36 (2003), 129–50; Adam
Mosley, ‘Objects of Knowledge: Mathematics and Models in SixteenthCentury Cosmology and Astronomy’, in Sachiko Kusukawa & Ian Maclean
(eds), Transmitting Knowledge: Words, Images, and Instruments in Early Modern Europe (Oxford, 2006).
On the move toward textbooks generally in the sixteenth century, see Charles
B. Schmitt, ‘The Rise of the Philosophical Textbook’, in Charles B. Schmitt
et al. (eds), The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy (Cambridge,
1988), 792–804; Campi, Angelis & Goeing, Scholarly Knowledge. Isabelle
Pantin has also identified 1495 as the beginning of a new phase of printed
commentaries in the Theorica genre: Pantin, ‘L’illustration des livres d’astronomie à la renaissance: l’évolution d’une discipline à travers ses images’, in
Meroi & Pogliano (eds), Immagini per conoscere, 8ff.
For example, Houghton gen typ 515.16.764, a volume that binds together
Lefèvre’s Textus de Sphera (Paris, 1516) with Ciruelo’s commentary Uberrimum sphere (Paris, 1498); Newberry (Vault) Ayer 6 .S2 1507 binds together
Lefèvre’s Textus (Paris, 1507) with Ciruelo (Paris, 1515). This combination is
42
22.
23.
24.
25.
26.
27.
28.
29.
30.
31.
History of Universities
also found in the library of Beatus Rhenanus as BHS [Bibliothèque humaniste de Sélestat] K950b.
This diversification holds true more generally for mathematics in the period;
see Brigitte Hoppe, ‘Die Vernetzung der Mathematisch ausgerichteten Anwendungsgebiete mit den Fächern des Quadriviums in der Frühen Neuzeit’,
in Irmgard Hantsche (ed.), Der ‘mathematicus: zur Entwicklung und Bedeutung einer neuen Berufsgruppe in der Zeit Gerhard Mercators (Bochum, 1996),
1–33.
In the second half of the sixteenth century, this genre dropped some of these
canonical texts, incorporating more sixteenth-century authors and growing
increasingly technical. Notable examples are Elia Vinetus, Sphaera emendata
(Paris, 1572) (which included commentaries by Gemma Frisius) and Clavius,
In Sphaeram Ioannis de Sacro Bosco commentarius. But collectors of mathematical books such as the French lawyer Jean I du Temps, active at the
beginning of the seventeenth century, still chose the edition of Giunta
published in 1531 to represent the tradition of Sacrobosco's Sphere, though
he supplemented it with the works of Oronce Fine on cosmography and
instruments. See Alexander Marr, ‘A Renaissance Library Rediscovered: The
“Repertorium Librorum Mathematica” of Jean I du Temps’, The Library 9
(2008), 428–70, entries 10 and 7, respectively (at pages 442–4). Marr argues
that du Temps’s library is more representative of mathematical libraries than,
for example, John Dee's or Bernardino Baldi’s.
Rival textbooks were written already in the thirteenth century by Grosseteste,
Peckham, and Campanus. Thorndike, The Sphere of Sacrobosco, 23–8.
On the title Cosmographia, see James Hankins, ‘Ptolemy’s Geography in the
Renaissance’, in Humanism and Platonism in the Italian Renaissance (2 vols,
Rome, 2003), i. 457–68. More generally, see also Zur Shalev & Charles
Burnett (eds), Ptolemy’s Geography in the Renaissance (London, 2011).
Larger cosmographies such as Sebastian Münster’s Cosmographia (1544)
bridge this genre with classical and medieval encyclopedic traditions. For an
account of these traditions, see Matthew McLean, The Cosmographia of
Sebastian Münster: Describing the World in the Reformation (Aldershot,
2007), 47–105. On the character of cosmography in this period, see Adam
Mosley, ‘The Cosmographer’s Role in the Sixteenth Century: A Preliminary
Study’, Archives internationales d’histoire des sciences 59 (2009), 423–39.
Fine designed the titlepage for Simon Colines’s new edition of Lefèvre’s
Textus de Sphaera when Colines took over the press from Henri Estienne in
1521. The press continued to produce the book, with newly added marginalia, to 1538.
Sir William Sherrington, The Endeavour of Jean Fernel (London, 1946), 18.
Robert of England described the ‘invention of a clock’ in his eleventh lecture on
Sacrobosco’s Sphere. Thorndike, The Sphere of Sacrobosco, 180–1 (translated at
230–1).
Sacrobosco, Sphaera mundi (Venice, 1490), a4r-a5r.
Lefèvre, Textus de sphera (Paris, 1495), a3r.
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
43
32. In fact, this short treatise was chapters 4, 5, 15, and 3 (in that order) of the
Elementa astronomiae of Geminus. Despite a partial Latin translation by
Giorgio Valla from 1490, it was mostly read in the full Latin translation by
Thomas Linacre (Venice, 1499). It is discussed in Georg Joachim Rheticus’
Wittenberg lecture notes (1530s) so it was added early to classrooms. For
more bibliography, see Robert B. Todd, ‘Geminus and the Ps.-Proclan
Sphaera’, in Virginia Brown (ed.), Catalogus translationum et commentationum
8 (Washington DC, 2003), 12–15.
33. On Copernicus’ reading, see bibliography in Robert S. Westman, The
Copernican Question: Prognostication, Skepticism, and Celestial Order (Berkeley, 2011), chap. 2. Westman also eloquently displays the value of studying
the whole range of astronomy textbooks, not simply the most innovative or
advanced works.
34. Eugene F. Rice Jr (ed.), The Prefatory Epistles of Jacques Lefèvre d’Étaples and
Related Texts (New York, 1972), 112–14.
35. Ibid., 391–5.
36. On Beatus as humanist, see François Heim & James Hirstein (eds), Beatus
Rhenanus (1485–1547): lecteur et éditeur des textes anciens (Turnhout, 2000).
On Glareanus, see the recent studies assembled by Iain Fenlon & Inga Mai
Groote (eds), Heinrich Glarean’s Books: The Intellectual World of a SixteenthCentury Musical Humanist (Cambridge, 2013).
37. As David Lines has argued, it is unhelpful to contrast ‘universities’ (or
‘scholastic’) with ‘humanist’: David A. Lines, ‘Humanism and the Italian
Universities’, in Christopher S. Celenza & Kenneth Gouwens (eds), Humanism and Creativity in the Renaissance: Essays in Honor of Ronald G. Witt
(Leiden, 2006), 327–46. Glareanus too was a humanist who spent most of
his life teaching in universities.
38. Beatus’ books bought during his grammar school and universities studies
are listed in Gustav Knod, Aus der Bibliothek des Beatus Rhenanus: ein
Beitrag zur Geschichte der Humanismus (Leipzig, 1889). A comparison of
their annotations may be found in Richard J. Oosterhoff, ‘Mathematical
Culture in Renaissance Paris: University, Print, and the Circle of Lefèvre
d’Étaples’ (PhD Dissertation, University of Notre Dame, 2013), Appendix
C, 410-12. Foundational studies of Beatus’ student notes are Emmanuel
Faye, ‘Beatus Rhenanus lecteur et étudiant de Charles de Bovelles’, Annuaire des Amis de la Bibliothèque Humanist de Sélestat, 1995, 119–38;
Emmanuel Faye & Michel Ancey, ‘Le cours de métaphysique de 1504 pris
en note par Beatus Rhenanus au Collège du Cardinal Lemoine. Édition et
traduction des propositions 1 à 3’, Annuaire des Amis de la Bibliothèque
Humanist de Sélestat, 1995, 139–42; Emmanuel Faye, ‘Nicolas de Cues et
Charles de Bovelles dans le manuscrit “Exigua pluvia” de Beatus Rhenanus’, Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du moyen âge 65 (1998),
415–50.
39. In fact, would-be bachelors were not even inscribed in the university rolls
until they graduated, and were solely registered in their respective colleges.
44
40.
41.
42.
43.
44.
History of Universities
See, for example, the register edited by James K. Farge, ed., Students and
Teachers at the University of Paris: The Generation of 1500. A Critical Edition
of Bibliothèque de l’Université de Paris (Sorbonne), Archives, Registres 89 and 90
(Leiden, 2006). The actual practice at Paris is probably mirrored in the more
detailed statutes of universities in Northern Europe that were founded by
Parisian masters in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, such as the universities of Cologne and Vienna (for an example, see discussion below of
Cologne). See Michael H. Shank, ‘Unless You Believe, You Shall Not Understand’: Logic, University, and Society in Late Medieval Vienna (Princeton,
1988), 35–6. Compare the statutes also at Erfurt: H. Wissenborn (ed.),
Acten der Erfurter Universität, (2 vols, Halle, 1881), ii. 134. For a fuller
discussion of the requirements at Paris, see Oosterhoff, ‘Mathematical Culture in Renaissance Paris’, 56–61.
H. Denifle & E. Châtelaine (eds), Chartularium universitatis Parisiensis (4
vols, Paris, 1889–97), ii. 678. ‘Item, quod audivistis centum lectiones de
Mathematica ad minus’.
Book of the Chancellor: fol. 5r, 6r-v, cit. Charles Thurot, De l’organisation de
l’enseignement dans l’Université de Paris au Moyen-Âge (Paris, 1850), 51: ‘Istud
per facultatem sic est interpretatum, quod sufficit audivisse unum librum
mathematicae, sicut tractatum de sphera, et alium librum actu audire cum spe
audiendi usque ad finem sine fraude’.
The Sammelband is BHS K 1046, including: (a) Lefèvre et al., Epitome in
libros arithmeticos (Paris, 1503), (b) Jordanus Nemorarius & Lefèvre, Elementa arithmetica, musicae (Paris, 1496), (c) Sacrobosco, Textus de sphera
(Paris, 1500). Hereafter, ‘Beatus’ Sacrobosco’.
The recent study of Glareanus’ library and annotations begins with Iain
Fenlon, ‘Heinrich Glarean’s Books’, in John Kmetz (ed), Music in the
German Renaissance: Sources, Styles, and Contexts (Cambridge, 1995),
74–102; Cristle Collins Judd, Reading Renaissance Music Theory: Hearing
with the Eyes (Cambridge, 2000), 130–76. More recently, see Fenlon &
Groote (eds), Heinrich Glarean’s Books; Anthony Grafton & Urs Leu, Henricus Glareanus’s (1488–1563) Chronologia of the Ancient World: A Facsimile
Edition of a Heavily Annotated Copy Held in Princeton University Library
(Leiden, 2013).
The statutes of Cologne are in Franz J. von Bianco, Die alte Universität Köln
und die spätern Gelehrten-Schulen dieser Stadt, i: Die alte Universität Köln
(Cologne, 1856), 68. ‘Item talis [Bacalarius temptandus] debet audivisse ultra
illos in aliquibus Scolis publicis alicujus Universitatis in qua protunc fuerunt
quinque Regentes magistri in artibus, libros infrascriptos: Physicorum ex
toto; de celo et mundo; de generatione et corruptione; Metheororum; parva
naturalia quo ad quatuor libros; de sensu et sensato; de sompno et vigilia, de
memoria et reminiscentia; de longitudine et brevitate vite; Spheram mundi;
Theoricas planetarum; tres libros Euclidis; Perspectivam communem; aliquem tractatum de proportionibus, et aliquem de latitudinibus formarum; et
aliquem in musica; et aliquem in aritmetica. Et sex libros Ethicorum et
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
45.
46.
47.
48.
49.
50.
51.
52.
53.
45
metaphisicam’. The statutes go on to specify how long most of these books
should be ‘read’ for.
Munich, Universitätsbibliothek, Inc.lat. 310#6. Hereafter ‘Glareanus’ Sacrobosco’. I have not examined the Sammelband, and I use the digital version
available at <http://epub.ub.uni-muenchen.de/11720/>.
Iain Fenlon & Inga Mai Groote, ‘Heinrich Glarean’s Books’, in Fenlon &
Groote (eds), Heinrich Glarean’s Books, 303–34, 322, nos. 60 and 61.
Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, B1r. ‘Velut Americus Vesputius qui usque ad circulum antarcticum fere passim duxit [ . . . ] Vide latius Americum Vesputium in
Cosmographia’.
Cosmographiae introductio cum quisbusdam geometriae ac astronomiae principiis
ad eam rem necessariis insuper quatuor Americi Vespucii navigationes universalis
Chosmographiae descriptio (St. Dié: [Vautrin Lud Nicolas Lud], 1507). Most
likely the book itself was composed by Matthias Ringmann, not his friend
Waldseemüller, though both contributed prefatory letters to the work: Franz
Laubenberger, ‘The Naming of America’, trans. Steven Rowan, The Sixteenth
Century Journal 13 (1982), 91–113.
For example, Jürgen Leonhardt has shown this for annotated Sammelbände
from Leipzig; ‘Classics as Textbooks: A Study of the Humanist Lectures on
Cicero at the University of Leipzig, Ca. 1515’, in Campi et al. (eds), Scholarly
Knowledge, 89–112. This practice should be distinguished from the equally
important practice of copying important annotations from one copy of a
book into another, especially famous for certain copies of Copernicus’ De
revolutionibus that circulated among Lutheran astronomers, including Tycho
Brahe: Owen Gingerich & Robert S. Westman, ‘The Wittich Connection:
Conflict and Priority in Late Sixteenth-Century Cosmology’, Transactions of
the American Philosophical Society 78 (1988), pp. i–148. The notes of Erasmus Reinhold and Jofrancus Offusius suggest a circle of disciples, but the
work’s difficulty makes it likely these were specialist readers, outside the
university context; see Gingerich, Annotated Census, pp. xix–xxi.
See Ann Blair, ‘Student Manuscripts and the Textbook’, in Campi et al.
(eds), Scholarly Knowledge, 39–74, 49; L.W.B Brockliss, French Higher
Education in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries: A Cultural History
(Oxford, 1987), 192; Françoise Waquet, Parler comme un livre: l’oralité et le
savoir, XVIe-XXe siècle (Paris, 2003).
Lefèvre, Textus de sphaera (Paris, 1500), BHS K1046c (i.e. Beatus’ Sacrobosco); BnF res.v.209; Glogoviensis, Introductorium compendiosum (Cracow,
1513), in the private collection of Owen Gingerich.
Jacques Lefèvre d’Étaples, Josse Clichtove & Charles Bovelles, Epitome
compendiosaque introductio in libros arithmeticos (Paris, 1503), BHS 1046a,
titlepage. ‘Est Beati Rhynavv Eschletstattini 1.4.0.3 Parrhisiis. Ma[nu] pro
[pria]’.
Inga Mai Groote & Bernhard Köble, ‘Glarean the Professor and His Students’ Books: Copied Lecture Notes’, Bibliotheque D’ Humanisme et Renaissance: Travaux et Documents 73/1 (2011): 61–91; Inga Mai Groote, Bernhard
46
54.
55.
56.
57.
58.
59.
60.
61.
62.
63.
64.
65.
History of Universities
Köble & Susan Forscher Weiss, ‘Evidence for Glarean’s Music Lectures
from His Students’ Books: Congruent Annotation in the Epitome and the
Dodekachordon’, in Fenlon & Groote (eds), Heinrich Glarean’s Books,
280–302, 293.
Cited and translated by Anthony T. Grafton and Urs B. Leu, ‘Chronica est
unica historiae lux: How Glarean Studied and Taught the Chronology of
the Ancient World’, in Heinrich Glarean’s Books, 248–79, 262. ‘Glareanus
Lectori: Quae nostra manu huc pinximus, studiose lector, etiam atque
etiam tecum meditare ac tuae infigas memoriae, videbis magnum huius
rei tibi fructum, ac velut tibi apertam, ad omnia in hoc libro sequentia,
ianuam’.
Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, B1r. ‘Sed meminerit Lector, inhabitabilem diceris
zonam quae vix inhabitatus potest, hinc verum poetae dixerant’.
The growth in number, size, and cultural importance of universities during
the sixteenth century is surveyed by Jacques Verger, ‘Patterns’, in Hilde de
Ridder-Symoens and Jacques Verger (eds), A History of the University in
Europe, i: Universities in the Middle Ages (New York, 2003), 35–68.
Beatus’ career as an exceptional corrector is outlined in Anthony T. Grafton,
The Culture of Correction in Renaissance Europe (London, 2011), passim.
Such manuscript notes are described by Owen Gingerich, ‘From Copernicus
to Kepler: Heliocentrism as Model and as Reality’, Proceedings of the American
Philosophical Society 117/6 (1973): 516–19.
The exception reveals how unusual this was at Paris: Jean-Patrice Boudet,
‘A “College of Astrology and Medicine”? Charles V, Gervais Chrétien, and
the Scientific Manuscripts of Maître Gervais’s College’, Studies in History and
Philosophy of Science 41 (2010), 99–108. On the early professorships of
mathematics at Padua and Bologna, see Paul F. Grendler, The Universities
of the Italian Renaissance (Baltimore, MD, 2002), 416–22.
I plan to address Harvey’s reading of Sacrobosco in another article.
Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a1v. ‘Mathemata inquit [Hermonymus] que (si Platoni
septimo de republica credimus) non modo rei publice litterarie, sed et civili
momentum habent maximum; et in his (ut sentit Plato) precipue erudiendi
sunt qui naturis sunt optimis’ (emph. Beatus). This letter is also published in
Rice (ed.), Prefatory Epistles, ep. 8.
Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a1v. ‘Mathematum non modica utilitas’.
Some of these motivations came from Nicholas of Cusa, whose theologia
mathematica became popular in Lefèvre’s circle: Stephan Meier-Oeser, Die
Präsenz des Vergessenen: Zur Rezeption der Philosophie des Nicolaus Cusanus
vom 15. bis zum 18. Jahrhundert (Münster, 1989), 36–61.
Mary J. [Henninger-]Voss, ‘Between the Cannon and the Book: Mathematics and Military Culture in Cinquecento Italy’ (Ph.D. dissertation, Johns
Hopkins, 1995).
Lefèvre d’Étaples, Textus de Sphera (Paris, 1495), a4r. On the phenomenon
generally, see Klaus Maurice, Sovereigns as Turners (Zurich, 1985); Horst
Bredekamp, The Lure of Antiquity and the Cult of the Machine. The Kunstkammer and the Evolution of Nature, Art and Technology, trans. A. Brown
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
66.
67.
68.
69.
70.
71.
72.
73.
74.
75.
76.
47
(Princeton, 1995); Alexander Marr, Between Raphael and Galileo: Mutio Oddi
and the Mathematical Culture of Late Renaissance Italy (Chicago, 2011), 155–9.
Ciruelo, D’Ailly & Sacrobosco, Uberrimum sphere mundi commentum, BHS
K950, a8v. ‘Hec spherae diffinitio ab Euclide Megarensi assignata, magis
fabricandae spherae modum industriam quamlibet, quare potius descriptio
dicenda est’.
Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, a2r. ‘Imaginetur quispiam hunc semicirculum circum
axem volui et sit spaera que ut prior diffinitio causalis est’.
John Brinsley, Ludus literarius; or, The Grammar Schoole (London, 1612),
quoted in Sherman, Used Books, 3–4. Erasmus of Rotterdam gave instructions for annotating in his ‘De ratione studii’, published in Collected Works of
Erasmus 2, ed. Craig R. Thompson (Toronto, 1978).
These heuristic categories are also found by Grafton & Leu, Henricus Glareanus’s (1488–1563) Chronologia, 19. See more generally Sherman, ‘What
Did Renaissance Readers Write in Their Books?’
Lefèvre, Textus de Sphera (Paris, 1500), BHS K1046c a[1]v. Beatus noted
Lefèvre’s first lines as a ‘Captatio benevolentiae’.
Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, B3r. ‘Veluti et horae euangelicae et horae passionis
Christi inchoantur ut Mathaei 12, de paterfamilias mittens operarios in
vineam suam, nonnullos hora primum, hoc est ortu solis, per secundum,
duas horas post ortum intelligit per undecimam unam autem solis occasum
intelligit. Quod ex fine parabolae depraehendis. Missi namque hora undecima operaverunt solum ad unam horam’.
Sacrobosco, Sphera cum commentis (Venice, 1508), Huntington, Burndy
751765, 61r. Lecture notes from 1573, by John Chambers at Oxford,
show extensive use of Cicero and other literary sources. These notes now
partially preserved in Oxford, Bodleian Library MS Savile 30. Cit. Robert
Goulding, ‘Testimonia Humanitatis: The Early Lectures of Henry Savile’, in
Francis Ames-Lewis (ed.), Sir Thomas Gresham and Gresham College (Aldershot, 1999), 143–4. Compare also Sacrobosco, Sphera cum commentis (Venice, 1508), Huntington 497564, 56r, where the reader reflects on the eclipse
seen in Jerusalem at Christ’s crucifixion.
Sacrobosco, Sphera cum commentis (Venice, 1508), Huntington, Burndy
751765, end guard page. Note that this reader would not have found Aristarchus’ heliocentrism in Vitruvius. It is reported in Archimedes’ Sandreckoner
and in Plutarch.
Beatus’ Sacrobosco, titlepage. ‘Provi.| Acuties intellectus quorumcumque
sensibilium instrumentorum virem supplet’.
Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, title page. ‘Astronomia est recta lex et regula superiorum corporum magnitudines et motus considerans’.
E.g., Thorndike, The Sphere of Sacrobosco and Its Commentators, 87, 91, 94,
95, inter alia. Readers commonly marked these passages: e.g. Pedro Ciruelo,
Uberrimum sphere mundi commentum (Paris, 1498), Newberry folio Inc.
8015, e.g. h4r-5r. In some cases they copied further lines from the ancient
author into the margin: Sacrobosco, Libellus de sphaera (Wittenberg, 1538),
BL 417.c.4, B5r.
48
History of Universities
77. Sacrobosco, Libellus de sphaera (Wittenberg, 1542), Houghton
*GC.04625.474tm, flyleaf. The reader titled the quotation from Metamorphoses 2.63–2.73, ‘Ovidius de duplici motu’.
78. Sacrobosco, Sphera cum commentis (Venice, 1508), Huntington, Burndy
751765. Many copies of this edition bear short lines of poetry on their
titlepages: BL IA.40072; Newberry VAULT Ayer 6 .S2 1507.
79. Lefèvre, Textus de Sphaera (Paris, 1516), Houghton GEN typ 515.16.764,
a4r. ‘quid est precedit quia est’.
80. A similar case is Sacrobosco, Sphera cum commentis (Venice, 1508), Huntington, Burndy 751765. There are systematically blocked out sections in
Pedro Ciruelo, Uberrimum sphere mundi commentum intersertis etiam questionibus domini Petri de Aliaco (Paris, 1498), Newberry folio Inc. 8015.
Readers often presented their notes in the argumentative form of questiones
or dubia. E.g.: Lefèvre, Textus de sphera (Paris, 1495), Huntington 105170.
81. Goulding, ‘Testimonia Humanitatis’.
82. Paolo Mancosu, Philosophy of Mathematics and Mathematical Practice in the
Seventeenth Century (Oxford, 1996); Timothy J. Reiss, Knowledge, Discovery
and Imagination in Early Modern Europe (Cambridge, 1997). The relevance
of logic and rhetoric for mathematical practice deserves further consideration,
following work by Giovanna Cifoletti, ‘From Valla to Viète: The Rhetorical
Reform of Logic and Its Use in Early Modern Algebra’, Early Science &
Medicine 11 (2006), 390–423.
83. Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, B1r. ‘Auctor noster loquitur secundum poetarum
sententiam, qui torridum eam dixerunt’.
84. Ibid. ‘inhabitabilem diceris zonam quae vix inhabitatus potest, hinc verum
poetae dixerant. Nam non multi sub torrida zona habitant’. On contemporary debates about the habitability of the torrid zone, see Christine
R. Johnson, The German Discovery of the World: Renaissance Encounters
with the Strange and Marvelous (Charlottesville, VA, 2008), 64–71.
85. This stance holds interesting implications for Glareanus’ view of scripture,
because elsewhere he quotes the Psalms as evidence for the earth’s stability,
citing the ‘regius poeta’. According to Glareanus, does scripture deploy the
same sententia poetarum as Virgil, and so speak less precisely than astronomers?
86. The emergence of the Empyrean and the tenth sphere is discussed in detail by
Edward Grant, Planets, Stars, and Orbs: The Medieval Cosmos, 1200–1687
(Cambridge, 1994), chap. 15, especially 376, 378–382.
87. Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a1v. ‘Preter hos celos naturales cognitos, sacri theologi
celum aliud empyreum, hoc est igneum, ponunt’.
88. Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a1v-a2r. ‘econtra autem alii influxum huius spherae
regens ipsam dicunt non pertinere ad ordinem mundi corporalis sed huius
celi tractatum, eo quod non via naturali sed sola fide et divina contemplatione
cognoscitur’.
89. Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a2r. ‘Moderni autem astrologi . . . viderunt stellas fixas
sive octavam spheram triplicem motum habere, que concludunt duas alias
spheras esse dandas preter octavam spheram’.
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
49
90. Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a3v. ‘Et hae proprio novem dicuntur orbes communi
vero spherae’. Beatus defended the common terminology as an example of
the species sometimes taking on the name of the higher genus it comes from,
citing the Topics I, and the examples of ‘dispositio’ used to mean both
‘dispositus’ and ‘habitus’, and ‘casus’ used to mean both ‘casus’ and ‘fortuna’, as described in Physics II.
91. Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a3v. ‘Quot autem sint secundum subiectam, numerus
apud philosophos est indeterminantus: secundum aliquos enim sunt Octo;
secundum alios, Novem, ut secundum autorem de sphera; secundum alios
decem’.
92. Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a3v. ‘Hoc etiam modo dispositio dividitur in dispositum et habitum, et casus dividitur in casum et fortunam, 2o Physicorum; et
respublica in regnam, optimorum gubernationem, rempublicam popularitatem, paucorum potentiam, Tyranidem et alias rei publicae species in 3o
Politicorum’.
93. Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a3v. ‘universum est una sphera non quidem simpliciter
accipiendo unum sed per aggregationem’.
94. Joannis Glogoviensis, Introductorium compendiosum in tractatum spere materialis (Cracow, 1513), private collection of Gingerich, sheet tipped in
between a3–a4. On the proper motion of heavenly spheres, see Aristotle,
De caelo II.8, inter alia.
95. Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, a4r. ‘David Poeta regius: Qui fundasti terram super
stabilitatem suam non inclinabitur in saeculum saeculi. Alio in loco dicitur
super maria fundavit eum et super fluviam preparavit eum’.
96. Sacrobosco, Libellus de sphaera (Wittenberg, 1542), Houghton Library *GC.
P4625.47tm, titlepage. The titlepage also indicates Capuchin ownership: ‘Ad
usum F.F. Capuccinorum Buhani 1666’. Many copies indicate Jesuit ownership; nearly half the copies I have seen bear an ex libris from religious houses.
97. Sacrobosco, Sphera cum commentis (Venice, 1508), Huntington, Burndy
751765.
98. Such readership evidence might balance narratives that stress the polarization of confessional natural philosophies, such as Sachiko Kusukawa,
‘Nature’s Regularity in Some Protestant Natural Philosophy Textbooks
1530-1630’, in Lorraine Daston & Michael Stolleis (eds), Natural Law
and Laws of Nature in Early Modern Europe: Jurisprudence, Theology, Moral
and Natural Philosophy (Aldershot, 2008), 105–22, 120.
99. E.g. Ann Blair, ‘Annotating and Indexing Natural Philosophy’, in M. FrascaSpada & Nicholas Jardine (eds), Books and the Sciences in History (Cambridge,
2000), 69–89. One of the most remarkable instances of such practices is the
pandechion epistemon of Ulisse Aldrovandi: see Fabian Krämer, ‘Ein papiernes
Archiv für alles jemals Geschriebene: Ulisse Aldrovandis Pandechion epistemonicon und die Naturgeschichte der Renaissance’, Zeitschrift für Geschichte
der Wissenschaften, Technik und Medizin 1 (2013), 11–36.
100. Anthony Grafton, April Shelford & Nancy G. Siraisi, New Worlds, Ancient
Texts: The Power of Tradition and the Shock of Discovery (Cambridge, MA,
50
101.
102.
103.
104.
105.
106.
107.
History of Universities
1992). Albrecht Dürer’s rhinoceros is a classic case, recently described by
Susan Dackerman, ‘Dürer’s Indexical Fantasy: The Rhinoceros and Printmaking’, in Susan Dackerman (ed.), Prints and the Pursuit of Knowledge in
Early Modern Europe (New Haven, 2011), 164–84. The slowness of this
process, enduring into the eighteenth century, is evident in Neil Safier,
Measuring the New World: Enlightenment Science and South America
(Chicago, 2008). On natural history specifically, see Brian W. Ogilvie,
The Science of Describing: Natural History in Renaissance Europe (Chicago,
2006). A similar point is made by Jed Z. Buchwald and Mordechai
Feingold, Newton and the Origin of Civilization (Princeton, 2012).
Esculano, Capuano, & Lefèvre d’Étaples, Sphera mundi cum tribus commentis (Venice, 1499), private collection of Owen Gingerich, titlepage: [of
Ciccho Esculano] ‘somnantis et delirantis’; [of Capuano] ‘excellentis ingenii
viri’.
For one example of cross-referencing within a collection, see Ciruelo,
Uberrimum sphere mundi commentum (Paris, 1498), Newberry folio Inc.
8015, b8r. Early modern readers valued editions that allowed them to
compare commentary and text traditions—a format which goes back to
the early Bible translations of Origen and Jerome—as can be seen in
polyglot editions of the Bible, but also side-by-side translations of Euclid:
Campanus & Bartholomaeo Zamberti, Euclidis Megarensis Geometricorum
elementorum libri XV (Paris, 1517).
Ciruelo, Uberrimum sphere mundi commentum (Paris, 1498), BHS K950,
b1r. ‘Huius opinionis est Faber Stapulensis’.
For example, see Beatus’ notes on the first flyleaves his Sammelband of
mathematical textbooks, BHS K1046, where he notes the pyramid or cone
as an analogy for the scale of being.
Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, e.g. A4r (references to the Bible, Ptolemy, Gregor
Reisch); A5r (Aristotle, De gen. et core.); B1r (Vespucci, from Ringmann’s
Cosmographia); B3r (the Bible); B6v (Vespucci from ibid., Ptolemy).
Around the time that he published this commentary in 1495, Lefèvre also
wrote a manuscript work De magia naturali, which described magic as the
‘practical part’ of natural philosophy. Within a few years, he spoke much
more carefully about magic as deceptive. For the most recent evaluation of
Lefèvre on magic, see Jean-Marc Mandosio, ‘Le De magia naturali de
Jacques Lefèvre d’Étaples: Magie, alchimie et cabale’, Rosanna Camos
Gorris (ed.), in Les Muses secrètes: kabbale, alchimie et littérature à la Renaissance, (Geneva, 2013), 37–79.
Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a8r. ‘Magi sunt super philosophos et sunt qui solerti
indagine ad secreta et arcana ipsius naturae investigant. et magia scientia est
qua naturae mysteria ingreditur. In qua inter nostrates Ioannes Picus
Mirandula maxime eluxit’. Note that Beatus (and presumably his master)
holds Pico as an authority in this area, even though it must have been
common knowledge that Pico denounced astrology in his Disputationes
adversus astrologiam divinatricem (Bologna, 1496). On the reception of
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
108.
109.
110.
111.
112.
113.
114.
115.
116.
117.
118.
51
Pico, see Steven Vanden Broecke, The Limits of Influence: Pico, Louvain, and
the Crisis of Renaissance Astrology (Leiden, 2003), 55–80.
Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a8r. ‘In deo sunt ideae omnium perfectarum
proprietatum’.
Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a8r. ‘Invisibilia enim dei (ut inquit Apostolus) a creatura mundi per ea que facta sunt intellecta conspicitur’. See Romans 1:20.
Lefèvre, Textus de Sphera (Paris, 1527), Houghton, f EC.Sa147s.1527, a5r.
‘4or secundum Cicerone lib. de natura deorum 2o’. Likely the intended
reference was Cicero, De natura deorum II xxxvii.97: ‘An, cum machinatione quadam moveri aliquid videmus, ut sphaeram ut horas ut alia permulta, non dubitamus quin illa opera sint rationis’. Similarly, the marginalia
of Sacrobosco, Libellus de sphaera (Wittenberg, 1538), BL 417.d.4, B4v,
B5r.
Lefèvre, Textus de Sphera (Paris, 1527), Houghton, f EC.Sa147s.1527, b1r.
‘de magica descript. Cael Cardin. vid. Cornel. Agrip. Arbatel, etc’. Spuriously attributed to Agrippa, probably edited by Theodore Zwinger, Arbatel
was first published in 1575 (Basel).
Sacrobosco, Libellus de sphaera (Wittenberg, 1542), Houghton *GC.
P4625.474tm, at cap. 1. ‘In definitioni Euclides sumpta ex translatione
Campani describa cum formalem spherae quo fiat’. | ‘In theodisii tales est in
principio Arg’.
Sacrobosco, Libellus de sphaera, Houghton *GC.P4625.474tm (B2r), in
which a reader quotes from a Greek edition of De caelo et mundo, giving
two definitions of kosmos.
I suggest this because the iconography for air used here is quite distinct, with
an undulating line commonly used elsewhere to represent clouds. Glareanus’ representation of air closely matches that found in the Venetian
tradition of these diagrams.
This image is typical in the Venetian tradition, but not found in either of
the other two books Glareanus copies illustrations from (as described
below).
Versions of this image were widely available in both manuscript and printed
copies of Sacrobosco (e.g. MS Ambrosiana C 241 Inf., 152r). However, the
illustration in Glareanus’ other edition of the Sphere does not have a tower,
the ship faces the other direction, and the earth’s bulge is hardly prominent.
Although it is possible that Glareanus coincidentally modified his own
drawing to match the widely available Venice editions, I think it more likely
that this is a visual quotation.
Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, b6r. ‘Propter spatii tamen indigentiam non omnia
luculentissime elaborata conspicis. Sed labore nostro lector contentus bene.
Vale’.
Esculano, Capuano & Lefèvre d’Étaples, Sphera mundi cum tribus commentis
(Venice, 1499), BnF res.v.199: [on image of c. mundi and c. eccentrici] ‘pro
hac lectione opertet videre theoricas planetarum georgii purbachii hec sunt
in hoc volumine’.
52
History of Universities
119. Besides Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, these figure are repeatedly copied in Lefèvre,
Textus de sphaera (Paris, 1521), BnF res.v.209, fol. 6r; Glogoviensis, Introductorium compendiosum in tractatum spere materialis (Cracow, 1513), collection of Owen Gingerich, B3v.
120. On visualization, see especially Crowther & Barker, ‘Training the Intelligent Eye’.
121. Isabelle Pantin, ‘Kepler’s Epitome: New Images for an Innovative Book’, in
Sachiko Kusukawa & Ian Maclean (eds), Transmitting Knowledge: Words,
Images, and Instruments in Early Modern Europe (Oxford, 2006), 217–38,
especially 229; Barker & Crowther, ‘Training the Intelligent Eye’, 448–51.
122. Joannes Sacrobosco & Wenceslaus Faber de Budweys, Opus Sphericum
Ioannis de Sacro Busto Figuris et Perutili Commento Illustratum (Cologne,
1508), BL IA:12221, a3r. Adam Mosley reflects on the role of instruments
in pedagogy in ‘Spheres and Texts on Spheres: The Book-Instrument
Relationship and an Armillary Sphere in the Whipple Museum of the
History of Science’, in Liba Taub & Frances Willmoth (eds), The Whipple
Museum of the History of Science: Instruments and Interpretations (Cambridge, 2006), 301–18.
123. Lefèvre, Textus de sphaera (Paris, 1500), BHS K1046c, a2v. Other copies
with similar notes include: Lefèvre, Textus de sphaera (Paris, 1521), BnF res.
v.209; Sacrobosco, Libellus de sphaera (Wittenberg, 1542), Houghton
*GC.04625.474tm.
124. Lefèvre Textus de sphaera (Paris, 1500), a7r-v.
125. Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a1v. ‘Convexum solis duplatum reddit 7930000, qui
multiplicatus per 22 [est] 174460000, et divisus per septem facit 24933851,
et restat unus denarius sive una 9a.’ N.B. that 7/22 was since antiquity the
standard approximation of the ratio of a circle’s diameter to its circumference.
126. Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a1v. ‘Dividendo circumferentiam celi solis que est
24833857 per 360 facit 6923, et restant 57 loco quorum ponutur integrum
in libro scilicet 69231’.
127. E.g. in the example given just now, Beatus miscopied the value for the
circumference, which is given in the text as 24933857.
128. Beatus’ Sacrobosco, a7r. ‘Quemadmodum littera minimum quid est in
grammatica, et vox seu dictio similiter minimum in logica, ita digitus
minimum quid in ea disciplina que de mensuribus et ponderibus est’.
129. On this aspect of Lefèvre’s pedagogy, see Richard J. Oosterhoff, ‘Idiotae,
Mathematics, and Artisans: The Untutored Mind and the Discovery of
Nature in the Fabrist Circle’, Intellectual History Review, (2014), 5–6.
130. A relevant perspective on Poliziano’s philological encyclopedism is found in
Jean-Marc Mandosio, ‘La classification des sciences et des arts à la Renaissance: Ange Politien, L’Omniscient (Panepistemon, 1492): édition, traduction et commentaire’ (Doctoral Thesis, École pratique des hautes études,
1998).
131. Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, A4r. ‘Ptolemaeus autem (ut auctor est Gaeorgius
[sic] Reisch in Marg. Philoso.) uni gradui respondere dicit stadia 500, quae
A Book, a Pen, and the Sphere
132.
133.
134.
135.
136.
137.
138.
139.
140.
141.
142.
143.
144.
53
per gradus caeli 360 multiplicata illum stadiorum numerum producunt
180000’.
Thorndike (ed.), The Sphere of Sacrobosco, 81.
This is a puzzling identification—one would assume, from the diagram, that
by ‘B’ Glareanus means l.
Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, A3r.
John Peckham, Perspectiva communis (Venice, 1504), 4r.
Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, A4r. ‘Hoc quod de Astrolabio hic dicit, non intelliges; in hoc videris, nam facile est hoc videre in astrolabio’.
Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, A5v. ‘Et hoc pulchre in corpore sphaerica videri
potest, et in plano depingi difficile’.
Glareanus’ Sacrobosco, B2r. ‘Lector probare hanc depingere difficillimum
puto. Longe enim in solido magis quam in plano haec conspicies. Ne igitur
tempus inutiliter confuseremus, consulto missa faecimus’. At the bottom of
the same page he similarly promised that a three-dimensional model would
make the example plain: ‘Haec si luculentius videre velis in rectu habes in
solide corpore conspicere, quoniam in planum figere hoc laboriosum invenies’ (If you want to see this more clearly, regarding the right [ascension],
you should look at a solid sphere, because you will find this more difficult to
set up here, on a plane).
Houghton f EC.Sa147s.1527, a Sammelband comprising Lefèvre, Textus de
sphera (Paris, 1527); Jean Fernel, Monalosphaerium, partibus constans quatuor (Paris, 1527); Jean Fernel, Cosmotheoria, libros duos complexa (Paris,
1528).
Many diagrams are clarified with short descriptions: e.g. Newberry VAULT
Ayer QB41 .S12 1508 no. 1; BL 417.d.4.
E.g. BnF res.v.209 (Paris, 1521), 13v; Huntington, Burndy 751765 (Venice, 1508), fol. 55v; BL 8562.f.34 (Paris, 1534), fol. 29r.
On the genre, see Anthony T. Grafton, ‘ Geniture Collections, Origins and
Uses of a Genre’, in Frasca-Spada & Jardine (eds), Books and the Sciences in
History, 49–68. See also Nicholas Popper, ‘The English Polydaedali: How
Gabriel Harvey Read Late Tudor London’, Journal of the History of Ideas 66
(2005), 351–81.
A classic description of the growing technical literature is Elizabeth Eisenstein, The Printing Press as an Agent of Change: Communications and Cultural
Transformations in Early-Modern Europe (Cambridge, 1979), 520–75. Some
sense of the growing genre can be seen in the bibliography assembled in Eva
G.R. Taylor, The Mathematical Practitioners of Tudor & Stuart England
(Cambridge, 1954). Printed technical books are only the most visible
portion of a rich culture of mathematical practitioners, as argued by Stephen
Johnston, ‘The Identity of the Mathematical Practitioner in 16th-Century
England’, in Hantsche (ed.), Der ‘mathematicus’, 93–120.
Anthony Grafton & Lisa Jardine, From Humanism to the Humanities:
Education and the Liberal Arts in Fifteenth- and Sixteenth-Century Europe
(Cambridge, MA, 1986).
54
History of Universities
145. Lefèvre, Textus de Sphaera (Paris, 1527), BL 533.k.1.
146. Lefèvre, Textus de Sphaera (Paris, 1527), Houghton f EC.Sa147s.1527,
titlepage.
147. Cf. Lefèvre’s prefatory letter to his Astronomicon, a contribution to the
theoric tradition: Rice, Prefatory Epistles, 112–14.
148. On the language of utility to support the rising prestige of mathematics, see
Katherine Neal, ‘The Rhetoric of Utility: Avoiding Occult Associations for
Mathematics Through Profitability and Pleasure’, History of Science 37
(1999), 151–78; Lesley B. Cormack, ‘The Commerce of Utility: Teaching
Mathematical Geography in Early Modern England’, Science & Education
15 (2006), 305–22.
149. Gingerich, ‘Sacrobosco Illustrated’, 211.