Published in 2010 by I.B.Tauris & Co Ltd
6 Salem Road, London W2 4BU
175 Fith Avenue, New York NY 10010
www.ibtauris.com
Copyright © Kostas Vlassopoulos, 2010
he right of Kostas Vlassopoulos to be identiied as the author of this work has been
asserted by the author in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patent Act 1988.
All rights reserved. Except for brief quotations in a review, this book, or any
part thereof, may not be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a retrieval system,
or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying,
recording or otherwise, without the prior written permission of the publisher.
ISBN (HB): 978 1 84511 844 0
ISBN (PB): 978 1 84511 845 7
A full CIP record for this book is available from the British Library
A full CIP record is available from the Library of Congress
Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: available
Typeset in Garamond Pro by Ellipsis Books Limited, Glasgow
Printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Antony Rowe, Chippenham
Contents
INTRODUCTION:
Ancients and Moderns
What is politics?
CHAPTER I: WHO SHOULD RULE?
he reception and transformation of the ancient vocabulary
CHAPTER II: THE EXERCISE OF POWER: LIBERTY
Modern times
CHAPTER III: POLITICS AS ACTIVITY: PARTICIPATION,
DELIBERATION, CONFLICT
he moderns
CHAPTER IV: THE ENDS OF POLITICS: THE GOOD LIFE,
A BETTER WORLD
he moderns
ix
xvi
xx
1
14
40
51
76
93
117
126
EPILOGUE
142
NOTES
146
INDEX
165
CHAPTER I
Who should rule?
he question of who should rule and the classiication of political systems
according to who rules are by no means natural to political thought. Many
political systems have existed without ever raising the issue. he ancient
Romans practised politics and even wrote about them without ever asking
the question, until they came to adopt, very sparingly, some terms and questions of Greek political philosophy.1 To all means and extents the question
and the terminology associated with this question were a Greek invention.
As a matter of fact, it also took a long time before the question arose
in Greek political thought. Until the ith century BCE the important questions for Greek political thought were rather diferent.2 For the archaic
Greeks the main question was whether a political community was wellordered or not; they thus distinguished between two diferent conditions,
eunomia (good order) and dysnomia (bad order). he question of who exercised power within the community was irrelevant and there was no available terminology in order to distinguish between diferent regimes; what
mattered was only whether the citizens thought that their community was
governed well.3 he archaic period was also characterised by the emergence
of individuals who came to monopolise power in their hands; the Greeks
called these individuals tyrannoi, from which the modern word tyrant
derives. his monopoly of power and oice in the hands of a single individual was strongly resisted by the rest of the traditional ruling classes, who
believed that power should be shared between political equals. heir slogan
was isonomia, the equal share of power. Isonomia could describe all forms
1
V
politics: antiqVity and its legacy
of political regimes in which power was not restricted to the hands of a
single individual. hese communities could vary widely in their political
forms. In some, power was concentrated in the hands of a few elected
magistrates or a council; in others, the citizen assembly had wider powers,
but only the propertied had the right to participate in the assembly, while
the poor citizens were excluded; in others, inally, the poor had the right
to participate in the assembly, but not the right to be elected to oice.
here were no terms available to distinguish between these diferent regimes;
the important thing was that, when contrasted to tyranny, they all appeared
to be systems of isonomia.4
his way of thinking changed rapidly with the emergence of democracy
in Athens during the ith century BCE.5 he exercise of power continued
to be seen as a reward for those who most contributed to the community
in words and deeds. But in the course of the ith century a new contender
for the reward of power emerged. We have seen how military service in
defence of the community was of paramount importance in justiication
of claims to power. he new Athenian superpower was not, though,
dependent so much on its infantry, traditionally consisting of the rich and
the middle class, but based its power on the navy, manned by thousands
of sailors who belonged to the lower classes. he claim that the lower classes
deserved to rule, because they contributed most to the defence and power
of the community, is irst presented to us by a ith-century author that
scholars traditionally call the Old Oligarch.
First I want to say this: there the poor and the people generally are
right to have more than the highborn and wealthy for the reason that
it is the people who man the ships and impart strength to the city;
the steersmen, the boatswains, the sub-boatswains, the look-out oicers, and the shipwrights – these are the ones who impart strength
to the city far more than the hoplites, the high-born, and the good
men. his being the case, it seems right for everyone to have a share
in the magistracies, both allotted and elective, for anyone to be able
to speak his mind if he wants to.6
2
who should rule?
But it was not just the fact that a novel claim to power could be substantiated. It was also the case that the functioning of the political system had
changed in a very fundamental manner.7 he political and social elite had
no power anymore to take decisions on its own. Instead, all important decisions in Athens were taken by the assembly, in which every citizen, no
matter how poor, had the right to participate, speak and vote. Furthermore,
while rich Athenians had to pay taxes or personally cover the expenses of
a number of state functions, poor citizens paid no taxes and received the
beneits of these services. To disgruntled members of the old political elite,
this looked like a form of government in which power rested in the lower
classes and was exercised to promote their class interest. hese disgruntled
members of the elite soon came with a name for this novel regime: they
called it demokratia, which meant that power (kratos) was in the hands of
the people (demos). But who exactly were the people? Like in modern
languages, the Greek word demos can be understood in two ways, one horizontal, the other vertical. In the horizontal way, the people are seen as
encompassing the whole citizen body; in the vertical the people are seen
as the lower classes and contrasted with the upper classes, the rich, the aristocracy or the rulers. he diference is clearer in the Latin language, which
distinguishes between the populus (horizontal) and the plebs (vertical).
hose who initially coined the term demokratia, used the term people in
the sense of the lower classes; in their eyes it was nothing more than the
rule of the poor over the rich.
hus, the emergence of democracy led to the discovery that political
systems could be classiied according to which individual or group was
holding power. Furthermore, political systems could be divided between
those that aimed at the common good, and those perverted versions which
merely aimed at the good of the rulers. A regime was classiied as a monarchy,
when there was a single ruler who governed according to the common
good; but it was classiied as a tyranny, when the single ruler governed in
his own interest. Equally, a regime was called an aristocracy, when rule was
in the hands of the best citizens (aristoi), who governed with the common
good in mind; but when the few (oligoi) governed in their own interest, it
3
V
politics: antiqVity and its legacy
was called an oligarchy. Interestingly, there was little agreement in terminology when it came to the government of the many. Democracy could be
used to describe both the good and the perverted version. he good version
could be also called politeia (polity), while the bad version could be called
ochlokratia, mob rule. he ambiguity was the result of the fact that democracy could mean either the rule of the people as a whole or of the lower
classes only.8
Let us concentrate on the concept of democracy for the time being. he
view of democracy as the rule of the lower classes became a staple of Greek
political thought and found its most emphatic expression in the work of
the fourth-century BCE philosopher Aristotle:
he argument therefore seems to make it clear that for few or many
to have power is an accidental feature of oligarchies in the one case
and democracies in the other, due to the fact that the rich are few
and the poor are many everywhere, but that the real thing in which
democracy and oligarchy difer from each other is poverty and wealth;
and it necessarily follows that wherever the rulers owe their power
to wealth, whether they be a minority or a majority, this is an oligarchy,
and when the poor rule, it is a democracy.9
he spectre of class rule by the lower classes haunted many opponents of
democracy and remained inluential until well into the twentieth century.
here was also an equally critical view of democracy which, however,
put things in a diferent light. In this conception democracy was not the
equivalent of class rule, but was identiied with lack of rule, with anarchy.
Its most memorable depiction was presented by Plato in his Republic:
‘Is it not the excess and greed of [liberty] and the neglect of all other
things that revolutionises [democracy] too and prepares the way for
the necessity of a tyranny?’ ‘How?’ he said. ‘Why, when a democratic
city athirst for liberty gets bad cupbearers for its leaders and is intoxicated by drinking too deep of that unmixed wine, and then, if its
4
who should rule?
so-called governors are not extremely mild and gentle with it and do
not dispense the liberty unstintedly, it chastises them and accuses
them of being accursed oligarchs . . . Is it not inevitable that in such
a state the spirit of liberty should go to all lengths?’ ‘Of course’. ‘And
this anarchical temper’, said I, ‘my friend, must penetrate into private
homes and inally enter into the very animals . . . And do you note
that the sum total of all these items when footed up is that they
render the souls of the citizens so sensitive that they chafe at the
slightest suggestion of servitude and will not endure it? For you are
aware that they inally pay no heed even to the laws written or
unwritten, so that forsooth they may have no master anywhere over
them’.10
his critical image of democracy as equivalent to anarchy remained
equally inluential in ancient and modern political thought. But even from
the beginnings of Athenian democracy in the ith century BCE, we come
across alternative deinitions that aim to defend democracy from its opponents. he earliest of them comes from the historian Herodotus, who
described a debate among Persian grandees about what form of regime they
should adopt ater the death of the legitimate monarch. Ater criticising
the excesses of monarchy and the danger of putting all power in the hands
of a single person, Otanes, one of the grandees, ofered the following account
of his preferred regime:
But the rule of the multitude has, in the irst place, the loveliest name
of all, equality, and does, in the second place, none of the things that
a monarch does. It determines oices by lot, and holds power accountable, and conducts all deliberating publicly. herefore I give my opinion
that we make an end of monarchy and exalt the multitude, for all
things are possible for the majority.11
Democracy was a polity in which all citizens were free and equal.
herefore, nobody had a better claim to rule than anybody else. Yet, decisions
5
V
politics: antiqVity and its legacy
needed to be taken and these decisions needed to be put into practice.
Democracy answered these needs by creating a political system in which
all citizens had an equal chance to participate in deliberation and to rule.
All important decisions were taken by the popular assembly, in which all
adult male citizens had the right to participate and speak. he magistrates
were merely executive oicials, who had no power to initiate policies or to
take important decisions on their own. hey were selected by lot annually,
among those citizens who wished to hold public oice. No citizen could
be selected twice for the same oice; thus, rotation ensured that no citizen
could become excessively powerful by continuous holding of oice. he
only exceptions were those functions that required special talents, like the
military and inancial oices. In these cases, the Athenians employed the
system of election instead of the lot and permitted re-election to the same
position without limit. But even these magistrates had no power to initiate
policy and were strictly within the power of the assembly.12
It is oten said that the diference between ancient and modern democracies lies in the fact that the former were direct, while the latter are based
on representation. While there is an important element of truth in this, it
is also highly misleading.13 Many important political decisions and functions were undertaken by representative bodies in Athenian democracy. Let
us briely look at two of them: the Council of the 500 and the popular
courts. he Council of the 500 was a representative body: each of the 139
districts of Attica was represented in the council in proportion to its
number of citizens. he Council prepared the agenda of the assembly: no
issue could be discussed in the assembly if it had not already been discussed
and put into the agenda by the Council. But councillors were selected by
lot, like the other magistrates, and no citizen could serve as councillor more
than twice in his life and even that non-consecutively.
he popular courts had important political functions, as we shall explain
in the next chapter. Every year 6,000 jurors were selected by lot from among
all citizens who wished to serve as jurors in that particular year. Cases were
heard by panels selected daily by lot from this pool of 6,000 jurors. Any
decision of the assembly could be challenged in court, and the jury had the
6
who should rule?
power to overturn it if found unconstitutional or inexpedient. he courts
were an important means of revisiting the decisions of the assembly, and
their decisions were inal, making some modern historians believe that they
were the true sovereign body of Athenian democracy.14 hus, important
political functions were undertaken not by the assembly in which every
citizen could participate, but by special bodies which represented the
Athenian citizens. But, in contrast to modern democracies, all these representative bodies were selected by lot and not by election. hus, the diference between ancient and modern democracies cannot be sought in
representation; it rather lies in the speciic role that representation and election play in modern democracies, a point to which we shall return later.
Classical Greece was characterised by an intense struggle between partisans of oligarchy and democracy. To avoid these constant ights, Greek
thinkers from the late ith century onwards came up with a new idea: the
mixed constitution. he idea was that one could avoid the excesses of every
single form and satisfy both democrats and oligarchs by combining elements
from the diferent constitutions into a single, mixed form. his was a very
potent idea in ancient, and later in modern political thought.15 Plato and
Aristotle, the earliest Greek thinkers to deal with the concept, tended to
see the mixed constitution as a mixture of monarchical, aristocratic and
democratic principles. hus, the mixed constitution should combine the
democratic principle of the lot with the aristocratic principle of election;
or it should combine the democratic principle of universal right to vote
for all citizens with the aristocratic principle that only certain citizens should
have the right to be elected into oice.16
But a new departure in political thought took place when Greek thinkers
tried to accommodate within this scheme some polities that were considered highly successful and could be seen as ideal examples of the mixed
constitution: initially Sparta, and later also Rome.17 Sparta and Rome could
not it easily into the usual classiication of Greek political thought.18 In
Sparta power was divided between the two kings, the senate (Gerousia),
the popular assembly and the ephors. he two kings were mainly in charge
7
V
politics: antiqVity and its legacy
of the army; the senate, made up of the two kings plus 28 Spartan citizens
over sixty elected for life, discussed all political afairs and brought proposals
for decision to the popular assembly. he assembly, in which all citizens
with full rights had the right to participate, could not discuss the proposals
put in front of it, but only accept them or turn them down. Finally, an
important role was played by the ive ephors elected annually from all the
Spartan citizens, but without the right of re-election. he ephors were seen
as a bridle on the power of the kings, and each month they swore an oath
of allegiance to the kings, valid for as long as the kings kept their own oath
of upholding the law.19
Rome had a similarly complex political structure.20 Power was divided
between the two consuls, the senate, the assemblies and the tribunes. he
two consuls were the annually-elected heads of the executive: chief among
their duties was military leadership. Once the consuls and other high
magistrates, like the quaestors, the praetors and the aediles, had inished their
term in oice, they became members of the Senate; the Senate was the only
deliberative body of the Roman state. However, the Senate did not have
any power to create new laws (legislative power) or to implement decisions
taken (executive power); its role was that of discussing policy and advising
the magistrates. Although its decisions were not legally binding, few magistrates ever dared ignore them. Legislation was in the hands of a variety of
diferent assemblies.21 he centuriate assembly (comitia centuriata), which
was the one that elected the consuls and other magistrates, was divided
into 193 centuries, with each century having a single vote. he citizens were
distributed among the centuries in a very unequal way, with the result that
the upper classes had a majority of the centuries, while a large proportion
of the citizens who belonged to the poorest class formed only a single
century. his gave the upper classes a strong control of the election of
magistrates. But, from the third century onwards, almost all legislative work
was not done by the centuriate assembly but was taken over by the tribal
assembly (comitia tributa), in which no class had a particular advantage.22
Roman assemblies could not deliberate on the proposals put in front of
them, but, like in Sparta, could only accept them or turn them down. Finally,
8
who should rule?
there were the plebeian tribunes, magistrates elected from among the
plebeians to protect their interests against the aristocratic patricians. he
tribunes had the right to imprison the consuls if they acted against the
interests of the plebeians and had a veto over the activities of the senate.
When Greek and Roman thinkers tried to classify Sparta and Rome as
mixed constitutions incorporating monarchical, aristocratic and democratic
elements, they efected a crucial transformation of the categories of Greek
political thought. Democracy, monarchy and aristocracy were originally
categories that described polities as a whole; when they became mere elements
of a mixed constitution, the road was open for a radical re-interpretation
of these concepts. his was particularly the case with Polybius, a Greek
statesman who wrote an important historical work to explain to his fellow
Greeks the reasons behind Rome’s meteoric rise to world power.23 According
to Polybius, the success of Sparta and Rome was due to their mixed constitution.24 he Spartan kings and the Roman consuls comprised the monarchical element. Monarchy, in his discussion of Sparta and Rome, did not
refer any more to the rule of a single individual; efectively, it had become
synonymous with executive power. he example of the Roman consuls,
which were considered as the monarchic element of the constitution, speaks
volumes in this respect. he discussion of executive power, as such, was a
novelty in Greek political thought. Previous discussions, like those of Plato
and Aristotle, had focused on participation and the legislative and judicial
powers. Now monarchy could be used to think about the implications and
problems of the executive power even within non-monarchical regimes.
In the same way, the Gerousia and the Senate represented the aristocratic element; thus, aristocracy or oligarchy was no longer understood as
a regime in which sufrage was restricted to only a segment of the citizen
body; it was now identiied with a speciic institution. Both the Spartan
Gerousia and the Roman Senate were elected bodies, whether directly or
indirectly, and, theoretically, they comprised just the wisest and ablest citizens; but one could easily make the move, as we shall see, of extending this
new image in order to view the senate as an organ comprising and expressing
the noble and the rich.
9
V
politics: antiqVity and its legacy
But the most important redeinition concerned democracy. One answer
to what was the democratic element in Sparta and Rome was on traditional
lines: it was the popular assemblies which, at the end of the day, decided
on all legislative issues. his answer would thus identify the democratic
element with direct popular participation in decision making. It is a distinctive characteristic of both Sparta and Rome that, in contrast to most ancient
aristocracies/oligarchies, all citizens had the right to participate in the legislative assembly. his would be of crucial importance for the future.
However, some ancient authors, when discussing Sparta, thought that
the democratic element lay rather in social practices.25 It was the equality
of life of the Spartan citizens that was the democratic element of their
constitution. It was not the mere legal equality that existed in a democracy
like Athens. In Sparta there was a public system of education and all citizens had to undergo the same training and live under the same conditions.
here were strict limits on the use of wealth, while citizens dined and spent
most of their time together in common messes.
But there was a third answer which would also prove of immense importance for the future. he democratic element could be seen as those magistrates or institutions which protected the interests of the people, the lower
classes: the ephors and the tribunes.26 he ephors and the tribunes were
elected without any limit of age or wealth and thus these oices were not
restricted to an aristocratic elite; in fact, in the case of the tribunes the
patricians were ineligible and only plebeians could be elected to the oice.
Both of them were seen as protecting the popular interest against the kings
and the consuls, and in the case of the tribunes against the patricians and
the senate as well.
hus, the attempt to locate the democratic element within the mixed
constitutions of Sparta and Rome provided two more ancient conceptions
of democracy: that of democracy as equality of social conditions and that
of democracy as the protection of the popular interests. his redeinition
of the key concepts of Greek political vocabulary was destined to have a
long aterlife. Plato’s and Aristotle’s version of the mixed constitution aimed
to unite democratic, aristocratic and monarchical principles in a novel and
10
who should rule?
unitary whole. In particular, they focused on how to redeine the citizen
body in such a way that it would avoid the extremes of either democracy
or oligarchy. he novelty of Polybius’s conception was that the issue of
political participation played little role in it; instead the focus was on speciic
institutions representing the diferent elements.27
here is one more essential thing to notice about the Greek classiication
of constitutions and their vocabulary of political rule. Because we still use
that vocabulary nowadays, we tend to consider it as natural and oten do
not appreciate its peculiarities. One of the most intriguing of these is that
it was not merely a typological description. he Greeks did not stop at
merely classifying diferent political forms; from the very irst appearance
of the diferent constitutions in the Persian Constitutional Debate presented
in Herodotus, they were presented as dynamic and mutable. hey possessed
their own inherent contradictions and had their own motors of change;
their contradictions and principles meant that each constitution was prone
to collapse and change into one of the others. According to the Persian
king Dareius, who is presented as a supporter of monarchy, both oligarchy
and democracy are inherently contradictory and their contradictions ultimately transform them into monarchies. he vying for authority and prestige among the political leaders in an oligarchy leads to conlict and faction,
from which inevitably a successful individual emerges, who creates a
monarchy. In a democracy, the people need leaders to stop corruption;
these demagogues gain prestige and ultimately subvert the constitution into
monarchy.28
his was a very elementary understanding of the mutability and contradictions of the constitutions. Later thinkers, notably Plato, Aristotle and
Polybius, presented very elaborate schemes of how constitutions were
subverted, what were their inherent contradictions and the process and
order by which one constitution was followed by another.29 Plato was the
irst political thinker to present a detailed description of constitutional
change, from his ideal state to timocracy, oligarchy, democracy and inally
tyranny.30 Plato was primarily interested in the supreme values that diferent
11
V
politics: antiqVity and its legacy
constitutions espoused and the process by which a form of rule was undermined and substituted by a diferent one. Aristotle disputed Plato’s claim
that there was a set pattern through which one constitution changed into
another; instead, he presented a very detailed and complex discussion of
the diferent ways in which constitutions could be transformed and of the
variety of reasons for which they were undermined. But it was Polybius
who presented what later became the most inluential pattern of political
change. According to him, the circle of constitutional change started from
monarchy, which through the excesses of later kings was turned into a
tyranny; once the tyrants were toppled, the regime would change into an
aristocracy of the best citizens, which in its turn, when its rulers became
corrupt and degenerate, would turn into an oligarchy governed by the rich;
the overthrow of the oligarchy would be followed by democracy, which,
due to the turbulence of the masses and the anarchy brought by the demagogues, would inally swing in full circle back to monarchy.31
Surprisingly, it was not Athens or Sparta but Rome that provided the
ideal testing ground for the dynamic and temporal character of the Greek
vocabulary. In contrast to the Greek cities, Rome was the only ancient
community which could be seen as having passed through the whole circle
of constitutional change. A plausible account could be written to show how
Rome had started as a monarchy under Romulus, had degenerated into
tyranny under Tarquinius Superbus, the last king, and was transformed
into an aristocracy with the abolition of monarchy and the creation of the
consuls; the creation of the tribunes, the abolition of patrician privileges
and the transfer of legislative power into the comitia tributa could be
portrayed either as the achievement of the mixed constitution, or as the
emergence of democracy; this was followed by the anarchy of the irst
century and Rome swung the full circle with the monarchy of Caesar and
Augustus.32 his pattern of change would create endless discussions among
later thinkers, who gave diferent assessments of the process, endeavoured
to discern the motor of political change and reached divergent conclusions.
As I said above, the distinction between diferent forms of political
rule was a Greek pastime that never occupied the Romans too much. he
12
who should rule?
Romans spent little time trying to diferentiate between the diferent
elements of their constitution or thinking more abstractly of who should
rule.33 What little discussion of the Roman polity from this perspective
is preserved comes mainly from Greek observers of Rome.34 Nevertheless,
the Romans possessed a political vocabulary, which would also play an
important role in modern political thought. he most important term of
Roman political vocabulary for our inquiry was the respublica. Respublica,
from which of course our modern word republic derives, means the public
concerns, the common issues.35 he early modern English translation of
the term as Commonwealth gives a good impression of its semantic value.
Respublica could be used to describe all political forms which pursued the
common good; it could thus encompass all three good constitutions of
the Greek vocabulary:
Respublica is the property of the people [res populi]. . . When the
supreme authority is vested in one man, we call him a king, and the
government of that respublica is a monarchy. When it is vested in a
select group, that respublica is said to be ruled by the power of an
aristocracy [optimatium]. he respublica in which everything depends
on the people is called a democracy [civitas popularis].36
While this was the meaning of respublica for the vast majority of Roman
authors, in a few cases it could be used in a more restricted sense. When
power in Rome was concentrated in the hands of the emperors, some Romans
thought that this was the end of the respublica, which was now substituted
by personal rule in the interest of the ruler and not for the common good.
he Roman historian Tacitus, for example, oten implicitly argued that the
republic was extinct ater the creation of the Principate by Augustus, and
he even stated that no-one born ater the battle of Actium had ever seen
the republic.37
his ambivalence of the term respublica would be of great importance
for the future. It should be here noted that a similar semantic shit had
taken place in the case of democracy as well. During the Hellenistic period,
13
V
politics: antiqVity and its legacy
the word democracy ceased to connote one of the six simple constitutions
and became the generic term for every polity that was not a monarchy, or
was independent from a king: thus, it could now cover both democracies
and aristocracies/oligarchies.38 his new meaning did not extinguish
completely older meanings of the term, which retained some of their hold
in more theoretical accounts, while being rather redundant in common
parlance. But the parallel shits of both republic and democracy to denote
all polities which were not monarchies would prove important.
To summarise, the Greeks invented a vocabulary to classify political
systems according to who was the ruler; to this, the Romans added the
concept of the respublica. hese diferent forms of rule were inherently
unstable and normally ended up in degeneration; many ancient thinkers
came to argue that only a mixed constitution, variously conceived, could
incorporate the positive aspects of the simple forms of rule, while also
solving their inherent contradictions. he vocabulary of rule was signiicantly modiied when it was used to identify monarchical, aristocratic and
democratic elements within a mixed constitution. Finally, we should note
the plurality of conceptualisations of democracy in ancient political thought:
direct popular rule, rule of the poor, anarchy, equality of social conditions,
representation of popular interests or a non-monarchical constitution.
he reception and transformation of the ancient
vocabulary
The world that followed the collapse of the Roman Empire, the barbarian
invasions and the loss of classical culture, was very different from classical antiquity. The world of the Middle Ages, fragmented in castles, principalities and kingdoms and dominated by feudal relations and obligations,
offered little scope for classical politics. But, from the later Middle Ages,
the political landscape changed significantly.39 The fragmented world of
the Middle Ages was gradually replaced by two different entities: the
largest part of Europe was now dominated by territorial kingdoms, like
France, England and Portugal; while in some areas, particularly the Italian
14
Index
Adams, John 30
Adoption xi–xiv, 1, 16–17, 20, 26,
59–60, 69, 94, 114, 126, 127–128,
137, 143
Ager publicus 136
Agis 122, 127
Agora 113
Agrarian laws 123–125, 127, 129, 135,
136–137, 139
America xii, 28–33, 34, 62–63,
103–105
Anarchy 4–5, 12, 14, 19, 23, 36, 48, 55,
59, 104
Ancients xvi–xviii, 64–67, 102,
104–105 and passim
Apathy 112–113
Appius Claudius xiii
Arendt, Hannah 113
Aretê xx, 77–78
Aristagoras 79
Aristides 91
Aristocracy xiv, xviii, 3, 7, 9, 10, 12, 13,
14, 16, 18, 19, 20, 22, 23–24,
26–27, 30, 33–34, 59, 64, 77, 79,
88, 100–101, 103, 107, 110, 129
Aristotle xii, xiv, 7, 12, 15, 22, 45, 56,
62, 72, 86–89, 94, 99, 114,
117–118, 126, 130, 138, 140–141
Army, standing 62
Athens ix, xv, xix, xxi, 2–3, 5–7, 10, 12,
19, 21, 25, 26, 30, 35–37, 43–47, 49,
50, 53, 56–57, 68, 73–74, 77–83,
84–85, 98, 104, 107, 109–111, 113,
114–115, 116, 119, 142
Augustine 145
Augustus 12, 13, 61–62
Auxilium 49
Aventine Secession xiii
Babeuf, G. 136–137
Berlin, Isiah 42
Blair, Tony 116
Brutus 91, 108
Bush, George W. 116
Caesar 12, 52, 62
Camillus 108
Canon xvi–xvii, 94, 97, 110
Castoriadis, C. 113
Cato 61, 63, 91
Censors 29
Cicero 56, 62, 63, 90–91, 94, 96,
125–126, 127, 130
Cincinnatus 108
Cleomenes 123, 127
Comitia centuriata 8
Comitia tributa 8, 12
Commerce 25, 63, 66, 101, 132, 133
Communitarianism xii, 114
Conflict xxi, 80–81, 82–84, 87–89,
103–105
Constant, B. 40–41, 70
165
V
politics: antiqVity and its legacy
Constitutional change 11–12, 19,
38–39
Contrast xiv–xv
Corcyra 83, 98
Corruption xiv, 11–12, 27, 46, 51, 61,
69, 71, 92, 93, 95, 103, 105, 107,
109, 119, 121, 122, 126, 131, 133,
135
Cromwell, Oliver 22–24, 128
Cursus honorum 90
French Revolution x–xi, xii, 21, 33–34,
69–70, 107–109, 136, 138–139
Deliberation 78–79, 81–82, 84–85,
90, 99–101, 106–107, 110–111,
115–116
Democracy xi, 3–4, 10–11, 13–14,
18–19, 22, 25, 28–39, 44–48, 56–57,
64, 73, 77, 80, 88, 102, 104, 107,
108, 110–111, 142
Demophilus 30
Demosthenes 44, 108, 110, 111
Dominium 58
Dysnomia 1
Habermas, Jürgen 115
Harrington, James 22–3, 62, 99–101,
128–129
Hebrews xvii
Hérault des Séchelles, Marie-Jean x
Herodotus 5, 11, 50, 79
Hobbes, Thomas xiv, xix, 56–59, 67,
97–99
Homer xx–xxi, 80, 117
Homoioi 120
Hume, David 65, 67
Hypereides 44
Germany ix
Gerousia 7, 101
Gordon, Thomas 61
Gracchi 27, 123, 124–125, 127, 136
Graphê paranomôn 82, 116
Green, T. H. 140
Grote, George 36, 73–74, 111
Egyptians xvii
Election 2, 6–7, 8, 29, 31, 32–33,
36–37, 88, 103–104
Empire xi, 49–51, 52–54, 63–64, 66
England 15, 20–24, 35, 54, 98, 131
Ephors 7–8, 10, 29, 54–55
Equality 1, 5–6, 10, 14, 22–23, 25, 30,
33–34,45, 47,49, 59, 67–69, 72, 74,
88, 105, 113, 120, 122–124, 133,
135, 136–137, 141
Eunomia 1
Idéologues 139
Isonomia 1
Ius 58
Jacobins 35, 40, 108, 138–139
Fascism xiii
Federalist Papers xii, 30–33, 103–105,
109
Fénelon, François xii, 129
Ferguson, Adam 65, 102–103, 132–133
Finley, Moses I. 80, 114
Florence 15, 52, 94, 96
France 15, 54, 55, 59–62
Freedom 40–42, 45, 47–8, 53, 56–57,
64, 65–67, 71, 72, 73–74, 75
Law 44, 58, 64, 81–82, 88–89
Lawcourts 6–7
Lawgiver x, 76, 89, 119, 120–121, 127,
128, 129, 132, 135, 137, 138, 139
Liberalism xii, xv, 46, 63, 70, 72–73,
139–141
Libertas 48–51
Livy xii, xvii, 16, 48–49, 62, 91, 99, 101,
103, 110
Locke, John 59, 62, 67
Logos 86
Lot 2, 5–6, 7, 36, 82
Lycurgus 24, 76, 89, 107, 108, 119–124,
127, 128, 135
166
INDEX
Mably xii, 69, 108, 135–136
Machiavelli, Niccolò xii, xiii, 16–19,
52–54, 94–96, 127
Mandeville, Bernard 131
Marius 62
Market 66, 113, 131–132, 133, 139
Marx, Karl x–xi, 39, 137–138
Matteotti, Giacomo xiii
Michels, Robert 114
Mill, John Stuart 73–74, 110–111
Minos x
Mirror of Princes 93
Mitford, William 35
Mixed constitution 7–11, 16, 17–18,
24, 25, 30, 32, 36, 89, 102
Models ix–x, xiii, xix, 16, 25, 26, 28, 29,
34, 36, 37, 55, 58, 62, 63, 68, 69, 84,
91, 94, 101, 103, 105–107, 108,
109–110, 113, 115, 118–125, 127,
129, 135, 137, 139, 143
Moderns xvi, xviii–xx, 64–67, 105–106,
139
Monarchy xi, 3, 9, 22, 25–26
Montesquieu 24–26, 34, 63–64, 70,
101–102, 109
More, Thomas 127–128, 135
Moyle, Walter 23, 35
Mussolini, Benito xiii
Napoleon x
Narratives xiv, xviii, 12, 23, 25–26,
61–62, 127, 139
Nazism 112
Nedham, Marchamont 21–22, 59–60
Nelson, Eric xvii, 141
Neville, Henry 23
Niebuhr, Barthold Georg 136
Numa 127
Nussbaum, Martha 141
Ober, Josiah 114–115
Oikos 113
Old Oligarch 2
Oligarchy xi, 4, 7, 9, 11, 12, 16, 20, 115
Otanes 5
Paine, Thomas 132, 151 n.82
Participation xx, 9–10, 11, 17, 19,
28–29, 32–33, 41, 45, 47, 68, 70, 73,
77, 81, 87, 112–115
Party xv, 104–105
Pelopidas 91
Pericles 77, 78, 84
Phocion 91
Physiocracy 135
Plato xii, xiv, 4, 7, 11–12, 47–48, 62,
75, 84–86, 108, 111, 112, 115–116,
120–122, 126, 127–128, 134, 140
Plebeians 20, 23, 49, 53–54, 95
Plutarch xiii, xvii, 62, 91, 101, 103, 110,
123–124, 127, 128, 135
Polis xx, 86–87, 130, 140
Politics xx–xxii, 84–86, 111
Polybius 9, 11–12, 16–17, 38, 52, 89,
95, 102, 142
Popper, Karl 112
Poverty 4, 78, 124–125, 135–136, 139
Proletarians 35
Property 58, 121–122, 126, 127–128, 136
Provocatio 49
Publius xii, 108
Rabaut de Saint-Étienne, J. P. 108
Rancière, Jacques 113
Rawls, John 140
Reform 112, 121, 123, 124, 127, 129,
137–138
Relevance xv, xviii, xix, 97, 105, 143
Religion 47, 54, 96, 106, 130, 144–145
Representation 6–7, 27, 29, 32–33, 68,
69–70
Republic xi, 13–14, 20, 24–26, 31
Rights 46–47, 57–59, 71–72, 130, 133,
136–137
Robespierre, M. x, 108
Rome xiv, 8–10, 12–14, 17–19, 20, 21,
23, 28, 30, 48–51, 52, 61–64, 69,
89–92, 95–96, 99–100, 103, 105,
108, 109, 110, 123–125, 127, 132,
136, 137, 142
Rosanvallon, Pierre 131
167
politics: antiqVity and its legacy
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques xiii, 26–28, 67–
69, 75, 105–107, 108, 133–135, 145
Saige, Guillaume-Joseph. 69
Saint-Just, Louis de x, 138
Sallust 50–51
Salutati, Coluccio 52
Senate 8, 9, 10, 18, 19, 22, 30, 59, 92,
93, 99, 123
Seneca 92
Service 76, 89–92
Slavery 42–43, 48, 65–66, 71–72, 133
Smith, Algernon 65, 131–132
Socialism xii, xiii, xiv, 34–35, 136–137,
140
Socrates 47, 104, 120
Solon xxi, 21, 43, 108, 127
Sovereignty xiv, 7, 26–28, 36–37,
56–57, 69, 98–99
Sparta 7, 9–10, 16, 22, 23–24, 25,
52–53, 68–69, 76–77, 100–101, 102,
105, 108–109, 119–124, 129, 132,
134–137
Stalinism 112
Stasis 80–81, 83
Sulla 52
Symbols xii-xiii
Tacitus xii, xvii, 13, 51, 61, 92, 97
Tarquinius Superbus 12
Thelwall, John 35
Thucydides ix, 77, 83–84, 97–98, 110
Terror 40, 70, 109
Timai xx
Tocqueville, A. de 34
Totalitarianism 112
Transformation xiv, 9, 17–18, 24–25,
26–27, 31–32, 37, 57–58, 59–60, 70,
77, 99–101, 102, 114, 127–128, 135,
137, 138
Trenchard, John 61
Tribunes 8–9, 10, 12, 18, 27, 29, 49,
53–55, 61, 96, 103, 137–138
Tyranny xi, 1–2, 3, 4, 11–12, 16, 20, 22,
24, 30, 36, 43, 44, 50, 53, 54, 60, 63,
69, 73, 81, 92, 104, 107
Utopia 127–128, 131, 134–135
Venice 15, 16, 17, 25, 94
Vigilance 62
Virtue xx, 77–78, 81, 82–83, 87,
89–90, 91, 92, 94–96, 99, 101–102,
103, 105–106, 108–109, 114,
119–122, 124, 125, 130, 131, 135,
141
Welfare state xii, 140
Whigs 60–62, 70
Williams, Bernard 71–72
Xenophon 119
168