1
WAS HEGEL AN ISLAMOPHOBE? AND WHY DOES IT MATTER?
Are Hegel’s views on Islam indicative of any discursive tendencies in modern
European views of Islam in world history? What does those views tell us about
the universality and atemporality of idealism (a view of reality as dependent on
human perception) as a philosophical discourse? If Hegel’s concept of Islam is
predicated on the ‘Orient’ – in the sense this notion was understood, and
practiced, in nineteenth-century Europe– how valid is this Hegelian legacy if
employed by modern and contemporary scholars in re-examining Islam after
September 11 and why should it matter now?
While answering these questions will not restore to intellectual history what
was lost on the battleground of Eurocentrism, it would still help pinpoint the
domains of power in which a hegemonic culture was mapped and its history
was imagined and constructed. The task here is not to label Hegelian thought
with Eurocentrism but to interrogate the intellectual premises that contributed
to the emergence of the Eurocentric and Orientalist elements in his thought.1
Let us begin by asking a clarifying question: why Hegel? Before attempting to
answer this question, it is important to emphasize that a clarification is not the
same as a justification and that embarking on ‘understanding’ Hegel does not
mean proving or conceding that he is right. There is always a haunting and
dynamic duality at work in every Hegelian sentence, which makes it difficult to
qualify him. The intricacy of his thought does not make process easier and
may indeed tip the scale of our interpretive task one way or the other.
Whatever the assessment of Hegel’s philosophical position on Islam might be,
there will always be room for second and third readings and a window for
doubt in order not to fall into the vicious trap of misunderstanding again. But
this does not mean that we should not start somewhere.
A major difficulty in grasping Hegel’s concept of history is that to him the real
is not what is out there in the phenomenological world. Geist (the mind or the
spirit) is the only reality for Hegel. Everything that takes place in the physical
world must be brought into relationship with the mind/spirit; even revolutions
must happen in the mind first: “World history begins with its universal goal:
the fulfillment of the concept of spirit. The goal is the inner, indeed innermost
unconscious drive, and the entire business of world history is the work if
2
bringing it into consciousness.”2 History for Hegel is therefore first and
foremost a mental process, an evolvement of self-consciousness and perception
as the mind opens itself through human history and civilization.
Hegel died in 1831, leaving behind him a corpus of idealist philosophy that
was to require centuries of unpacking and interpretations. Thanks to Hegel, an
academic discipline of history rose to unparalleled heights in nineteenthcentury Europe. Hegel left a tremendous impact on modern liberals, including
Marx, who was a devout member of the Young Hegelians as a youth and
deeply influenced by the new historical vein in Hegel’s philosophy. Later on,
Hegel’s views on Islam as a religion that seeks “world dominion” while
lacking particularity or nationalist inclinations would serve as a ground for
Marx’s analysis of Islam.3 Hegel believed that the state is a “primordial
institution of human life, like the family,” and that it was “closer to the divine
order than anything else on earth and therefore has the power to demand
compliance.”4 Hegel also revolutionized transcendental philosophy through a
radical self-critique of epistemology. In opposition to Kant, Hegel was able to
demonstrate the phenomenological self-reflection of knowledge as the
necessary radicalization of the critique of reason.5 This radicalization resulted
in a crucial moment in modern European thought when philosophy broke off
the borders of its closed academic circles to become a commentary on the
history of the world. In other words, theory and reality, transcendentalism and
phenomenology, converged at this historic juncture. Or, to put it in Hegel’s
language, the rational-freedom became real.
While there is a direct relationship between power and knowledge, it is worth
inquire about the bases and sources of that knowledge – not just how complete,
but also how cryptic and obscure it can be. Only with closer attention to the
production of the historical episteme and the narratives associated with it do
we begin to discern not only the anecdotes and fantasies but also the politics
that envelop the very source of such knowledge. Hegel is not an exception to
this rule and his use of terms like “absolutism” and the “Orient” has an
intriguing historical context to it that is worth investigating further.
The Roots of Hegel’s Absolutism
In his intriguing work Lineages of the Absolutist State, Perry Anderson dissect this
Foucauldian duality with reference to Hegel, albeit indirectly, through
undertaking a topic many historians would shy away from: identifying blind
3
spots in historical Marxism and philosophical Marxism, while attempting to
synthesize both in an unrivaled comprehensive attempt to reexamine the
European continent’s modern political history, East and West, from the lenses
of absolutism. To do so, he undertakes a radical historical contextualization of
the spheres of knowledge in nineteenth-century Europe. What Anderson
modestly refers to as “a comprehensive survey of the nature and development
of the Absolutist Sate in Europe” turns out to be not just a survey, but an indepth and thorough double-punch critique of Marxist empiricists who often
neglect theory and Marxist philosophers who engage in the theoretical issues
of historical materialism without paying much attention to the events of
history.6
Anderson’s study of “history from above,” and of the “particular” and the
“general” of Europe’s lineages of absolutism, sheds significant light on “the
first international State system in the modern world” 7 in a comprehensive way
that help us understand and situate the discursive practices that informed
Hegel’s philosophy of world history, although Hegel himself is not a major
aspect of Anderson’s critique. According to Anderson, the issue that the
serious historian must face is not only to detect forces and patterns of events at
work in the formation of political thought, but also to resist chronological
convenience and dominant customs of historiographic monism. Anderson thus
writes his work against the grain of structured historiography, with its
“common departure and common conclusion, spanned by a single stretch of
time.”8
The traditional view held by Marxism has been that history is a series of class
struggles ultimately rooted in economic conflict, though these struggles may
take political forms. These economic conflicts take place between an exploiting
class and an exploited class. Pointing attention to the infamous ambiguity of
Marx when it comes to the definition of ‘class’ and its retroactive applicability,
Anderson contends that as much as “history from below” is beneficial to both
Marxist and non-Marxist historians, “secular struggle between classes is
ultimately resolved at the political—not at the economic or cultural—level of
society.”9 To examine this “political level,” he introduces a typology rather
than a chronology of absolutism, one in which “periodization” is no longer the
only criterion for historical judgment and should not obfuscate the similarities
in the patterns and forces at work that produce the absolutist state in Europe.
Spanish absolutism, for example, ended in the late sixteenth century;
England’s lasted till the end of the mid seventeenth, and France’s till the end of
the eighteenth, while Prussia’s made it till the end of the nineteenth, and
4
Russia’s was only overthrown in the twentieth century. Still, Anderson
maintains, such absolutisms share a common ground: recurrent absolutism.
Anderson’s point is that despite the temporal spacing of absolutism, there are
essential thematic factors to be considered before we submit ourselves to
truncated theories of history that reduce it to class struggle. In the case of
Europe, and for the benefit of our approach to Hegel, these factors include the
accumulation of capital, religious movements and reformations, formation of
nations, the advent of industrialization, and the expansion of overseas
imperialism.
For the present context, it is most relevant to focus on some of the important
questions that Anderson’s study implicitly raises: why did Europe generate
“monarchy,” to use Montesquieu’s terms, whereas the Orient, or the Asiatic, is
only capable of producing “despotism”? What is so specific and unique to
European forms of political domination? Why does Europe tend to dismiss its
Eastern part when it writes its history? Was a warped line of Eurocentrism
drawn in the public texts of the Enlightenment? If so, how did this attempt at
demarcation influence the field of European intellectual history?
It is easy to see why an ‘advanced’ Western Europe would want to sever itself
from the Continent’s ‘backward’ regions. Still, Anderson confronts us again
with the lamentable fact that historical research on Europe focused either on
single countries or limited periods, and that historiography was conducted
mainly within national bounds. For Anderson, as long as we are unwilling to
interpret Western Europe’s political thought in a comparative relationship to
Eastern Europe and the Muslim Ottoman Empire, historical research, Marxist
or not, will remain confined to limited national frames.
Anderson’s contextual critique of absolutism is crucial for understanding how
Hegel built his philosophy of world history and how he treated Islam and its
tradition in his dialectical thinking, but also, and more importantly, how
‘Europe’ constructed its history in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. As
Anderson cleverly juxtaposes the genealogy of Europe’s classical engagement
with Greece and especially with its ‘feudal’ system and systematic segregation
from the House of Islam, he puts into question the very foundations and
formative premises of Europe’s nineteenth-century socio-political and cultural
heritage, making one wonder whether Western Europe’s early nineteenthcentury patronage of Greek nationalists against the Ottomans was an untimely
sign of Orientalist animosity towards an Islamic state that happened to be in
5
the heart of Europe. Anderson’s line of argument seems to lead to this
conclusion.
For example, he confronts the question of how it came about that “the
Ottoman State, occupant of South-Eastern Europe for five hundred years,
camped in the continent without ever becoming naturalized into its social or
political system.”10 The Ottoman Empire, continues Anderson, “always
remained largely a stranger to European culture, as an Islamic intrusion into
Christendom, and has posed intractable problems of presentation to unitary
histories of the continent to this day.”11 According to Anderson, the
investigation into Western Europe’s absolutism could benefit from
comparisons with Eastern Europe, one in which the formation of Ottoman
rule certainly stands out as a key example with which to contrast European
absolutism for multiple reasons: the physical presence of Islam in Europe, the
long history of military conflict between Islam and Christendom, and the selfunderstanding of Europe in relation to the “Orient.” The significance of
understanding Europe’s perception of itself in relationship to Turkey is
particularly important for the positioning of Islam within the matrix of its
intellectual history.
In Anderson’s view, it was Machiavelli in early sixteenth-century Italy who, in
two central passages of The Prince (published 1532), was “the first theorist to
use the Ottoman State as the antithesis of a European monarchy” by explicitly
condemning the Porte’s autocratic bureaucracy.12 A few decades later,
Machiavelli was followed by Jean Bodin who, in his Six Livres de la République
(1576) describes the King of the Turks as the “Grand Seignior,” a term used to
describe despotism avant la lettre, due to his dictatorship and sole complete
ownership of property. Another important blow dealt to the Ottomans was in
early seventeenth-century England at the hands of Francis Bacon (1561–1626).
In The Essays or Counsels Civil and Moral (1632), Bacon distinguishes Europe
from Turkey by emphasizing the latter’s social absence of “hereditary
aristocracy” that characterized European rule: “a monarchy where there is no
nobility at all, is ever a pure and absolute tyranny, as that of the Turks.”13 The
legacy of this distinction, argues Anderson, continued in figures like James
Harrington and François Bernier who criticized Ottoman economy. In fact, it
was in the Commonwealth of Oceana (1656) that Harrington further widened the
gulf of distinction by arguing that unlike Europe, the economic foundations of
the Ottoman Empire were based on matters of land monopoly.14 Bernier’s
Travels in the Mogul Empire (1671), the work that is known to have invented
racial classifications as such,15 cemented Harrington’s views and added a
6
scathing eye-witness travelogue of the Islamic empire as “barbaric” and
“uncivilized,” where cronyism, favoritism, and land monopoly roamed
unchecked. Bernier’s account was the first to dwell on a relationship between
biology and mental development and to leave a palpable mark on eighteenthcentury European historiography and influence such major thinkers like the
Baron de Montesquieu (1689-1755).
Despite Montesquieu’s famous opposition to slavery and colonial
expansion,16 he still saw a sharp distinction between Europe and Islam as
embodied in the Ottoman Empire: “There is no despotism so injurious as that
whose prince declares himself propertier of all landed estates and heir of all
subjects: the consequence is always the abandonment of cultivation, and if the
ruler interferes in trade, the ruin of every industry.”17 In addition, Montesquieu
went on to bestow a sense of geographical conditioning and atmospheric
doom, fashionable at the time, on all Asians and Orientals.18 Montesquieu’s
reputation as an ‘enlightened’ thinker was in every way conducive to making
his De l’Esprit de Lois (1758) Europe’s first geo-political gospel of Orientalism.
Although it was the despotic practices and corrupt reputation of the Ottoman
Sultan, “Grand Seignior,” that triggered Europe’s antagonism, this
particularity did not prevent Muslim subjects and Islam in general from
becoming the public target of Western enmity. With political despotism,
economic corruption, geographical fatalism now the fortifying walls separating
Europe from Islam, Europe left the Orient with only a few branches of
knowledge to claim as their own. Soon intellectual history would decide the
battle, as Hegel, the inheritor of the Enlightenment and of Montesquieu’s
binarisms, would use history to widen the gap of disparity between Europe and
the rest of the world. Now, if this indeed was the episteme that granted Islam
entrance into Hegel’s philosophy of world history, and if one were to speak
about the ideals of this history and grant oneself axiomatically the position of
thinking and deciding those ideals, how are we to judge the validity of such
ideals, especially when they were formed and informed by concepts of racial
and economic supremacy?
Situating Islam in Hegelian thought
Theodor Adorno once said of Hegel that his “genius relies in his mediatory
philosophy and in his attempt to define the spirit that prevails over mankind
but also prevails in them.”19 Paul de Man also confirms the existence of
unconscious Hegelianism in all of us:
7
Whether we know it or not, or like it, or not, most of us are Hegelians
and quite orthodox ones at that. We are Hegelian when we reflect on
literary history in terms of an articulation between a Hellenic and a
Christian era, or between the Hebraic and the Hellenic world. We are
Hegelian when we try to systematize the relationships between the
various art forms or genre according to different modes of
representation. Or when we try to conceive of historical periodization
as a development of a collective or individual consciousness.”20
To both Adorno and de Man, then, Hegelian thought is an all-inclusive
philosophical space in which currents of thought have been collected and
preserved. Contemporary interpretations of Hegel’s philosophy have also
assumed this position of comprehensive totalization. Take for instance
Adorno’s provocative reading of Hegel’s philosophy of history as consciously
paradoxical:
“It is characteristic of Hegel’s thinking that he really wants to have it
all ways: that he really wants to include everything, even things that
simply cannot be reconciled. By this, I mean that he adopts the
standpoint of the universal. He tends always to claim, ideologically
and in a conformist spirit, that the universal is in the right. But
equally, almost as an afterthought, he would also like to be credited
with wanting fair play for the individual. Incidentally, this comment
applies with equal force to the entire Hegelian macro-structure since
the whole point of his philosophy is that it not only teaches absolute
identity, but also believes that non-identity – in other words, the very
thing that cannot be included in identity – should somehow be
incorporated into the concept of identity in the course of its
elaboration.”21
In this passage Adorno touches upon the core of Hegelian thinking, namely its
antithetical inclusion or dialectical dynamism. According to this formula,
Hegel has already accounted for everything, and even the opposite of his
thought is a necessary component of the thought process. In other words, there
is no outside Hegel.22 And it is specifically in this context that we must
examine his philosophy. On the one hand, there is the claim of universalism,
the idea that Hegel’s philosophy transcends time and space and is therefore a
valid source of a better understanding of everything, including religion. On the
other hand, there is a phenomenological world with Haiti on the far horizon
8
and the Ottoman Empire next door, shelled in its own political, economic and
cultural “absolutism,” to insist on Anderson’s term. This phenomenality of
the “non-European Other” poses the following inevitable questions to
transcendental philosophy: was Hegel’s presentation of Islam done in a
manner typical of the compartmentalizing thought of 19th century Europe?
While there may not be a straightforward answer to this question that will
satisfy both the abstract Hegelian and the material Marxian23, one thing is
clear: Islam is manifest in Hegel’s concept of religion not as a religion, but as a
constituted “absolutism” serving the One. The way in which Islam is explained
in Hegel’s philosophy is not explored in a contextual or documentary fashion.
Instead, it takes place within an already-constituted framework of Hellenistic
Christianity in which already thought-of human beings behave in different
manners towards an already-designed sphere of knowledge. In this particular
sphere, Islam functions as a form of “fanaticism” to Hegel. We may say that
this reductive view of Islam is roughly analogous to so-called subjective
economics of thought, or to be more precise, a utility theory24 that seeks unity
through marginalization of its Others, one in which an understanding of a scalled “alien” religion from the perspective of an already constituted idealist
society is reached without properly inquiring into the way in which this
understanding has been constructed in the first place. At the very least, Hegel’s
analysis of Islam is lacking in philosophical reflection, making Hegel appear to
a seasoned and educated reader as a stereotypical representative of his own
age: a while European male concerned with the way in which an existing mind
relates to already-established facts. However, Hegel is not to be excused from
ignoring the purely subjective nature of history.
To his credit, Hegel knew more about the history of world religion than most
of his contemporaries, but it is not certain to what extent he was indeed
versatile in the available literature on Islam. Islam and the Arab world
represent a palpable epistemological lacuna and reference to Islam is made
carefully and tersely, as it is the case with Parts II and III of Lectures on the
Philosophy of Religion. In these two Parts, Islam appears as an existing adversary
to Christianity. There are also sporadic and almost repetitive allusions to Islam
in other lectures, such as Philosophy of World History, Philosophy of Art, and
History of Philosophy. In all of those scattered references, Hegel pays more
attention to a dominant or received impression of Islam without attending to
its original texts, subsequent developments, or contemporary living
expressions, or even careful documentation of his sources, quoting from
memory sometimes:
9
Religions have purpose—universal as necessity itself, but at the same
time empirical, external, and political in character. Islamic religion,
we are told, also has a world dominion as its purpose, but of a spiritual
rather than a political character.25
This “world dominion” in Islam, we soon find out, is motivated by what Hegel
sometimes refers to as “nationality,” and sometimes the “particularity of
religion,” but the word he often repeats is “fanaticism,” a trait that he believes,
not surprisingly for us now, to be also found in Judaism, albeit conditionally.
The following quote is an example of what Hegel believes to be a fundamental
difference between Islam and Christianity:
In Islam it is only being a believer that matters. This is not obstinacy
but fanaticism, because although nationality (natural associations),
family connections, homeland, etc. remain (limited connections,
stable relationships are permitted), the service of the One basically
involves the un-limitedness and instability of all subsistence. (God’s
acceptance has occurred once and for all, and what replaces
reconciliation or redemption is something that had implicitly
happened, a choice, an election by grace involving no freedom. We
have here a view grounded on power, a blind election, not an election
made from the point of freedom.26
Two words stand out in this extract: fanaticism and freedom. To be sure,
Hegel has a special use for fanaticism that is not equivalent to the dominant
use of the word today. He defines fanaticism as “passion for an abstraction,
for an abstract thought, which relates as negating force to the existing
object/thought.”27 Fanaticism, in other words, is as an obligation to bring
other people to the form of worship or religion. The fanatic in Hegel means the
practical, the passionate, the particular, the zealous, the proselytizer. So when
Hegel says that “fanaticism” is the goal of Islam, he means that the single
purpose of this religion is raised to a universal purpose, and only in its
obligation to spread and propagate itself does it become fanatical. But then he
also argues that fanaticism is found among the Jews and appears only when
their possessions or religion comes under attack, though without the
proselytizing impulse that defines Islam:
Jewish particularity, however, is not polemical because there is no
obligation to convert other people to the God of Israel. While others
10
are called upon to glorify the Lord, this is not a goal, as in Islam,
which is pursued with fanaticism. Judaism has become fanatical only
when attacked, only when its existence has been threatened.28
This quote is a perfect example of Hegel’s non-historcial and unstudied
assessment of Judaism. Some Jewish factions did encourage proselytizing well
into the second and third centuries if not later, but the dominance of
Christianity in the Roman world made such efforts increasingly difficult.
While we have less information about active missionizing to pre-Islamic
polytheists outside of the Pax Romana, the near universalism of Islam within a
generation after Muhammad had a similar stultifying effect on Judaism as the
Roman adoption of Christianity. Thus, it seems, Jews got out of the
missionizing business largely because the other, more politically-dominant,
monotheistic (Abrahamic) religions would simply not allow it.29 Hegel makes
no reference to Christianity, the missing third in the Abrahamic chain, in
relationship to fanaticism. On the contrary, Hegel’s Christianity is a religion of
freedom, whereas Judaism and Islam are religions of commandments as such,
where service is not rational for its own sake:
In any religion, such as Judaism or Islam, where God is
comprehended only under the abstract category of the One, this
human lack of freedom is the real basis, and humanity’s relationship
to God takes the form of a heavy yoke of onerous service. True
liberation is to be found in Christianity, in the Trinity.30
As for the second term, Hegel bases his theory of world history on the concept
of freedom. To Hegel, history itself is a development towards absolute
freedom: “It is this final goal—freedom—toward which all the world’s history
has been working. It is this goal to which all the sacrifices have been brought
upon the broad altar of the earth in the long flow of time.”31 Let us consider
this more carefully. Freedom is based on -- in fact constituted by -- human
reason. Hegel’s “goal,” then, means that freedom comes only after history, that
history is the development of human freedom, and that human freedom is
man’s consciousness of this freedom. This is how Hegel accounts for the
master-slave aufhebung (dialectic): in order to freedom to be achieved, it must
pass through the secular world of bondage and unfreedom. In other words,
freedom is not really freedom, but rather the consciousness of it. This
consciousness is what brings totality to life. But if this understanding of
freedom as conscious ‘understanding’ can be told with bias and
dematerialization, then Hegel’s project of universal freedom invites many
11
questions. Why, one might curiously ask, does Christianity have freedom
while Judaism and Islam do not? How do we understand and where do we
locate this freedom if it only exists in relationship and as a relationship to the
real? Part of understanding freedom in Christianity and part of Hegel’s entire
philosophical project, especially in the History of Religion, is to prove the
existence of freedom in Christianity and Greek religion through its lack in all
other world religions. In other words, freedom is defined negatively, which
could also mean, to use Hegel against Hegel, that freedom is not really ‘free.’
There is thus a crucial element in Hegel’s dialectical thought worthy of critical
attention. Hegel bases his whole logic on the hypothesis that everything which
exists can only be itself in relation, and – ultimately – as the relation to its
Other. In this manner of thinking Hegel’s definition of freedom can also be
counterintuitive. If Christianity can be defined by its difference from Islam,
how then is Christianity “freedom” when the basic premise of its freedom can
only be understood through its difference from other religions? Hegel has a
good explanation for this. As previously argued, history to Hegel is a
dialectical movement in the direction of freedom. This notion somehow allows
him to single out Greek and Christian religions as centers for this freedom.
Comparing Christianity and Greece to some Oriental religions, mostly Chinese
and Indian, which he heaps together, Hegel writes:
In the Eastern religions the first condition is that only the one
substance shall, as such, be true, and that the individual neither can
attain to any value in as far as he attains himself as against the being
in and for itself. In the Greek and Christian religion, on the other
hand, the subject knows himself to be free and must be maintained as
such; and because the individual this way makes himself independent,
it is undoubtedly much more different for Thought to free itself from
this individuality and to constitute itself in the independence.32
This theory of freedom as a status, one in which history will reach an end
according to Hegel, is highly vulnerable. How Hegel is able to equate Greece
with Christianity and to connect both to freedom is a complex and convoluted
process that took many twists and turns. Without having to dwell on Hegel’s
Grecianization of Christianity, it is still quite legitimate to interrogate the
validity of Hegel’s definition of freedom. The most vexed question is how we
come to experience this freedom not just as a physical state of “being free,” but
also on the level of the mind. Freedom is a receding telos and not an end in
itself, part of a coveted form of life that might not exist to us in the manner
12
Hegel conceives of it. Freedom, if we can grasp it, is only there in very limited
activities and for a very brief time. “Regardless of what happens,” argues JeanLuc Nancy, “it will be a question of bringing an experience of ‘freedom’ to
light as a theme and putting it at stake as a praxis of thought.” 33 In other
words, freedom must result from a confrontation with a phenomenological
given, or as Nancy puts it, “the testing of something real,” the object of
thinking and not thinking in itself, whose seizure “will always be
illegitimate.”34 There is something dangerous and risky about freedom, and
that is why we can easily fall into a guilt trap when we have too much
‘freedom.’ Even that which in our societies we call enjoyment – sports, fun,
recreation, vacation, time-off, unwinding – all such terms have become labels
of our consumer culture. Above all, freedom is a subjective experience, one
that is reduced to the possibility of staying alive.35
The questions we must ask are whether a philosophy of world history is
possible without a seemingly impossible totalizations; whether a definition of
an essentially subjective experience like freedom is possible without Hegel’s
Euronormative ‘fanaticism’ that surrounds and restricts its access to Christian
Europe and ancient Greece; and whether we can find pacifying epistemologies
to help us arrive at the objectivity of the spirit, without committing a grave
mistake against reason by finding meaning where it is quite possible that none
exists. This disposition towards Euronormativism, however, is not the most
striking in Hegel’s work. Rather, it is the brutal calculation with which he
dismisses all things Arab, Islamic, and “Oriental,” Take, for example, his view
on Arab philosophy:
The Arabians, moreover, made a point for the most part of studying
the writings of Aristotle very diligently, and of availing themselves
more especially both of his metaphysical and logical writings, and
also of his Physics; they occupied themselves particularly with
multiplying commentaries on Aristotle, and developing still further
the abstract logical element there present. Many of these
commentaries are still extant. Works of this kind are known in the
West, and have been even translated into Latin and printed; but much
good is not to be got from them.36
This obvious contempt for “Arabian” work on Aristotle reveals two facts.
First, the denigration of a “non-European” culture as superfluous and useless
in its translations and interpretation of Aristotle; and secondly, the claiming of
Aristotle’s philosophical heritage as Western intellectual property. Two other
13
important nineteenth-century factors in understanding the deeper implications
of the dismissal of Islam in relationship to the Greek tradition in Hegel’s
philosophy—note how Hegel cleverly uses the word Arabian here— are
xenophobia and monopoly of tradition.
A further, equally important component that we can detect in Hegel concerns
the geopolitics that Anderson’s Montesquieu established and Europe
uncritically adopted. The irony is that Eurocentrism and Euronormativism are
themselves specifically geopolitical constructs and calculated moves designed
to insert the newly established idea of Europe (although such geopolitical
categorization is neither adequate nor precise in capturing the constitutional
complexity of European politics). Yet this philosophically supported
geopolitics took place in a cultural context completely different from the one
that surrounded the events of September 11. The primary relevance here is not
the scholastic environment of nineteenth-century German philosophy or
European epistemology in general (a topic frequently discussed by Edward
Said and others) but the vicissitudes of European supremacy at the moment of
the colonial turn in epistemology.37
Hegel in Post-September 11 Islamophobia
Why then is a study of Hegel’s theory on Islam pertinent now? In order to
answer this question, let us examine some minor threads of the ramifications
of Hegel’s philosophy in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.
Albert
Hourani reminds us that “most of the historians and historical thinkers of the
nineteenth century were children of Hegel,” and that “the general concepts
which he represented could be developed in many different ways, with
differing emphases.”38 This is why Hegel matters to an understanding of Islam
in modern European thought. But what gets elided in this understanding, as
usual, is context. Yet precisely in this context the Germanic, or in this case, the
Prussian nation in which Hegel lived and practiced his philosophy of world
history, was able to envision for itself an inverted telos, a future in the past,
and to find its spirit, so to speak, in the older imperial theme of the Holy
Roman Empire, and thus its own identification with ancient Rome. This
religio-philosophical bond with older empires and Greek philosophy—we have
seen how Islam was removed from the frame—also played out in the German
classical engagement with Greece and especially with the movement of Greek
independence.
14
Let us consider a variation on this theme in a recent study of Hegel and Islam.
Weighing in on Hegel’s philosophy of history, Jean-Joseph Goux’s “Untimely
Islam: September 11th and the Philosophies of History” sets out to explain the
historical differences and the different historicities (views of history as
progressive, regressive, teleological, circular, or finite) that distinguish Judaism
and Christianity from Islam. A specialist in postmodern French philosophy,
aesthetic theories, and socio-symbolic interpretation, Goux analyzes the
“untimeliness” of Islam in the philosophies of history in this essay. Since our
study of Hegel is not solely from the inside, that is, not an expository or a
“continuist approach” like Goux’s, it will be useful to address the unexamined
context in Goux’s analysis of Hegel in the following paragraphs.39
Like many scholars attempting to understand the happenings of September 11,
Goux undertakes an in-depth critical revision of Islam’s position in history, a
position informed (he argues) by Christianity’s entrance into its third
millennium:
It is important, I think, to take a step back from an event whose
media impact, obsessive visual presence in our memories, and shortterm political effects run the risk of depriving us of an interpretative
framework. It seems to me that what is required to overcome 9/11’s
obnubilating and obfuscating effect (which is part of terrorism) is the
theoretical and speculative distance offered by the philosophies of
History.40
Goux's argument is resourceful, but as he goes on it seems to be an cryptic
exercise in Hegelian dialecticism. Drawing on a strong concatenation of
European thought on Islam (Turgot, Condorcet, Hegel) and taking the terrorist
attacks of September 11th as a springboard for his critical assessment, Goux
compares Islam to the West in order to expose “the many violent conflicts that
occur all along the “fault lines” between Islam and the West, which as he
emphasizes, “are not merely the expression of another type of historicity that is
destined to remain foreign to us,” but are also symptoms of “a profound
disruption in the traditional and secular relationship to historicity within Islam
itself.”41 Such “profound disruption” derives, as Goux continues, from the
awkwardness with which Western philosophies of history have treated Islam.
Hence the need for Hegel:
15
Thinking the Arab-Muslim world in the context of a philosophy of
History, assigning it a determinant place in the successive stages of a
universal evolution conceived as gradual or progressive, proved to be
awkward for thinkers such as Turgot or Condorcet, who, since the
Enlightenment, have endeavored to conceive the movement of
human societies as a whole. The thinker who confronted this
difficulty most lucidly was Hegel. And it was only by a seemingly
arbitrary chronological contortion—both highly significant and rich
in consequences—that Hegel was able to tackle this problem.42
Goux’s point is well taken. There is no gainsaying that Hegel found a place for
Islam within universal history in a way that his predecessors did not or could
not. But in order to understand how Hegel “tackle[d] this problem,” it is
crucial to explore the fields of force that made Hegel’s understanding of Islam
necessary at that particular time in European history. To Goux, Hegel offers a
quatrain theory of universal history which positions world ideas in light of
Geist (mind, spirit) according to the logic of internal necessity. In this
classification, the worlf of Islam falls under Hegel’s fourth category. Together
with the “Germanic World,” Islam belongs to the last stage of Geist. The first
category/stage, the “Oriental Empire,” includes China, Egypt, and Persia;
then comes the “Greek World” of ethical freedom, which represents the
adolescence of humanity. The third category includes the “Roman World” and
“Christianity,” both representing the now-predictable principle of abstract
universality:
As the highest intuition of the One, Islam thus occupies a rather high
position in Hegelian History; it belongs to the fourth and final stage of
Spirit in the tableau of Universal History. It therefore has nothing to
do with the Orient (in the Hegelian sense), which represents the
childhood or dawn of History. Islam belongs to the Western Spirit, to
the age in which this Spirit arrives at or returns to unity. Yet, this is
not its ultimate position, for as we mentioned above, this fourth stage
includes a bifurcation, a divergence that unfavorably distinguishes
Islam from a Christianity having reached the fully-realized version of
itself: Protestantism.43
This argument may well be convincing, but it should not be seen as clinching
the question of historical differential in the “Christianity-Europe” Hegelian
dialectic. In addressing the ‘bifurcation’ in Hegel’s fourth stage of human
history, Goux explains Islam’s devotion to ‘Oneness’ with its relinquishment
16
of, or indifference to, the secular world. This Hegelian ‘indifference’ is what
distinguishes Islam from Christianity. Christianity, Goux argues, as he
continues to interpret Hegel, is unique in the sense that its consciousness and
subjectivity create a different, more positive relationship to the secular world,
one that is interested in lifting it up from its primitivism and barbarism:
Whence this divergence? Islam remains within the abstraction of
spirituality. One must fear and honor God, the One, and adhere to
this abstraction. God is an absolute in the face of whom man has no
other end, no particularity, nothing individual. This entails an
indifferent attitude toward the secular world, which is left to its
primitivism and its barbarism, and which remains foreign to Spirit
and does not reach the consciousness of rational organization. . . .
This is where the divergence with Christianity appears. In
Christianity, the consciousness and will of Subjectivity as the divine
personality appear in the world as an individual subject. This
consciousness then develops itself until it reigns as true Spirit. Thus in
Christianity the spiritual goal can be realized in the secular world.44
In Goux’s analysis, Christianity is a vivid representation of God on earth,
although divinity in Hegel is a much more complex category than Goux
implies in his essay. According to Goux, it is this representation of human
divinity, so to speak—both in its power and vulnerability—that Islam lacks
and that makes Christianity realizable in the secular world. Using this postulate,
Goux goes on to explain what could have otherwise been “a violent offense to
chronology, a kind of outrageous anomaly” in Hegel’s philosophy of history.
Goux argues that Hegel deliberately puts Islam on a deceptively elevated stage,
only to reveal the religion’s disinterestedness in the secular world. But this
argument forgets that Hegel’s reference to Islam is epistemologically illinformed and overlooks the fact that Hegel is a phenomenological dialectical
thinker when he approaches the seemingly abstract notion of Islam.
Goux’s approach to Islam invites some interesting questions. Why should one
believe that there could have been a distortion and anomaly in Hegel’s
categorization of Islam? Why would Islam’s commitment to an abstract deincarnated “Oneness,” its “centeredness” around “the abstraction of
spirituality,” and its “fear of God” be interpreted as an “indifferent attitude
towards the secular world”? What does the ‘secular world’ mean to Hegel?
Moreover, if “indifference” to the ‘secular world’ does indeed exist in Islam,
what does this “indifference” imply and how is it different from the Judeo-
17
Christian perception of the material world? Goux argues that Christianity, or
Hegel’s understanding of Christianity, breaks away from Islam precisely
because of the former’s attention to worldliness. In Hegel, Islam’s opposition
to “barbarism,” though a latecomer among monotheistic religions, still
“develops more quickly than Christianity—which needed all of eight centuries
before it grew into a worldly form.”45 Likewise, “the principle of the Germanic
world became a concrete reality only through the Germanic nations.”46 This
means that Islam is not on a different plane from the Germanic world, as
Goux claims. In fact, the two examples of the fourth stage of world history
explain and complement each other. The fourth stage is not solely Germanic,
but medieval as well.
Islam’s medievalness, Hegel explains, is like old age in nature, but which must
not be taken as natural weakness of dotage, since it is the realm of the Spirit.
The medieval Germanic stage of world history is “the old age of the Spirit in
its complete ripeness, in which Spirit returns to unity with itself, but as
Spirit.”47 Hegel defines Islam in this sense as absolute freedom, as “the
enlightenment of the oriental world.”48 Moreover, Islam becomes the West (in
the Hegelian sense of the West, i.e., consciousness of Geist as a free spirit). It is
important here to emphasize that the secular world in Hegel is also the world
of “brutal barbarism,” which the Spirit finds itself in and “builds up as an
implicitly organic outward being” to reach “freedom,” the one and only goal
of world history.49
If Islam is not “indifferent” to the secular world, but is indeed freedom from
the ecclesiastical authority of the “Church” or the “State,” does this leave us
with the possibility that Goux misunderstood Hegel, or that Hegel’s
philosophical views on Islam are far less epistemologically damaging than
Goux’s? Is Islam better off misunderstood by Hegel than by Goux? After all,
Hegel wrote about Islam in a different atmosphere and did not use a terrorist
event as a springboard for his critique.50
The answer to above questions is no. Like many scholars who specialize in
Western philosophy, Goux offers a well-meaning attempt to find in the
Hegelian idea of world history an answer to Islam’s “collision” with the
Western world today, arguing that such an answer derives from a
philosophical discourse that Goux knows very well and believes is capable of
encapsulating the totality of the human experience. Goux’s invocation of
Hegel’s engagement with Islam derives from an urgent need to account for a
dangerous collision of two temporalities:
18
This collision-effect or untimely upsurge that has often been
produced—and even more so today—in the relations between the
West and the Arab-Muslim world are rooted in and separated by two
very different relationships to narrative and to History. It is thus
important in this context to address the two-fold question of Islam in
History and History in Islam. This question is, of course, too large to
be appropriately addressed in an essay. Nonetheless, six years after
the events of September 11th, the question deserves at least to be
posed. We ought to add that, beyond the terrorist attacks of
September 11th, the many violent conflicts that occur all along the
“fault lines” are not merely the expression of another type of
historicity that is destined to remain foreign to us; that are also
perhaps the symptom of a profound disruption in the traditional and
secular relationship to historicity within Islam itself.51
In all good intent, Goux wishes to take a moderate position between extremes.
But exactly what type of question is a “question of Islam in History and
History in Islam?” Does Goux refer to Islam in Hegelian history? World
history? Or does he speak about Islam in history in general? And what type of
history? Intellectual? Universal? Anthropological? How does a vague question
about Islam in history immediately conflict with a vaguer question about
“history in Islam?” Does it even follow that Goux’s reference to September 11
is an “example” of “untimely Islam,” as he proposes? To read Goux’s text as
an instance of ideological discourse is to attribute a political force to it. Rather
than resorting to speculative philosophies of history that are foundationally
suspect, let alone empirically impossible to prove, one must ask harder
questions about whether or not Hegel’s offers an unparalleled and detached
transcendental single philosophy on Islam or whether he himself is an
integrated set of practical knowledge that can neither be understood nor
understand itself outside of its particular context. Are we then to understand
Islam as a religion that cares only for the vertical (heaven) at the expense of the
horizontal (worldly future) and takes the past as an example to follow,
abandoning any care for earth and its inhabitants — hence September 11? Are
we to infer from Goux’s so-called ‘Hegelian’ interpretation that Islam is a
religion lacking a worldly or secular telos and therefore heedless of life and its
beings? The real burden that philosophy places on us is not to invoke,
erroneously that is, a theory of intellectual history sunk in Eurocentrism and
apply it anachronistically to an event that has nothing to with Islam.— but to
embrace the postulate that sources within “Western philosophy” are indeed
responsible for producing this divide in the first place.
19
This said, Goux’s argument is not necessarily culture-specific. It does not
state as fact a world that is inhabited by self-contained and uniform cultural
identities, each possessing a separate value, although his structuralist analysis
of Hegel falls within this “fault line.” Nor does it presume that Hegel’s
philosophy distinctively expresses a “Western” form of historical reason that is
impenetrable to the Islamic ‘Other.’ Herein lies the illusionary synecdoche and
the confusion of the part (Hegel/Europe/bin Laden) for the whole (the
world/Islam). The danger in this metonymic ‘symbolist’ mode of thought that
Goux adopts is that even a truncated ‘philosophical’ reading of September 11
requires a historical context, and one should not rely only on a ‘formalist
application’ of Hegel without a radical contextualization of Hegel himself.
To give Goux the benefit of the doubt, his analogy is perhaps exercised in good
faith and perhaps even from a deeper conviction than a so-called ‘universal’
theory of intellectual history accepted in his intellectual circle that supposedly
has all the answers to today’s global problems. This view—that the future is
always already accounted for in some sacred past (be it religion or
philosophy)—makes some scholars feel comfortable, that an all-inclusive
theory like Hegel’s is capable of explaining fundamentalism today. But it is
precisely this faith in the unconditional recyclability and infinite applicability
of the philosophical tradition that is alarming. There is no safe anachronistic
theory of this sort, and therefore no escape from repeating the same set of
misconceptions if we treat derivatives as if they were substance merely because
this is the only way we have been taught to think and this is the only language
that we think we understand.
Notes
1
Some recent studies have traced elements of racism and bias in Hegelian philosophy as well as post-Hegelian
thought. Susan Buck Morss, for instance, has convincingly debunked Hegel’s position on slavery and exposed
his racial bias, taking the philosopher down from the ivory tower of idealism to the realism of street-talk, coffee
shop gatherings, and morning newspaper culture. See Susan Buck-Morss, Hegel, Haiti, and Universal History
(University of Pittsburgh Press, 2009). See also “Hegel and Haiti”: Critical Inquiry, Vol. 26, No. 4 (Summer,
2000), pp. 821-865. Ian Almond has also dwelt on Hegel’s philosophy and its persistent continuity in works of
contemporary thinkers like Slavoj Žižek. See Ian Almond, “Iraq and the Hegelian Legacy of Žižek’s Islam,”
The New Orientalists: Postmodern Presentations of Islam from Foucault to Baudrillard (London: I.B. Tauris, 2007)
176-195. See also Frantz Fanon, The Wretched of the Earth, trans. Constance Farrington (New York, 1968). In
his book, Fanon interrogates European philosophy to expose European (white) hegemony. He uses both Marx
and Freud to re-interpret Hegel’s master-slave dialectic in order to theorize the necessity of violent struggle by
20
Third World nations. According to Fanon, who worked and lived in Algeria during the French occupation,
colonized nations seek to overcome colonialism as well the duplicitous humanism of Western Europe, so that
they could attain equal recognition in terms of their own cultural values.
2
G.W.F. Hegel, Introduction to the Philosophy of History, trans. Leo Rauch (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing
Company), p. 27.
3
For more on Hegel’s influence on Marx’s views on Islam, see Rosalind C. Morris, “Theses on the Questions
of War: History Media, Terror”: Social Text 20.3 (2002) 149-175.
4
Here we must clarify Hegel’s reference to Christianity. For Hegel, Catholicism became a reactionary and
conservative force that was chained by traditional and institutional “medievalism.” If anything, Hegel was in
favor of Lutheranism because it leaves room for academic contemplation and penetrative analysis of the
universe. On Hegel’s views on Christianity and Catholicism, see Lawrence S. Stepelevich, “Hegel and Roman
Catholicism”: Journal of the American Academy of Religion, Vol. 60, No. 4 (Winter, 1992), pp. 673- 691.
5
G.W.F. Hegel, The Phenomenology of the Spirit; see also Jürgen Habermas, Knowledge and Human Interests.
Trans. Jeremy Shapiro (Boston: Beacon Press, 1968), pp. 3-24, and George Mosse, The Culture of Western
Europe (Westview Press, 1988), pp.148-158.
6
Perry Anderson, Lineages of the Absolutist State (London: NLB, 1974), p. 7.
7
Ibid., p. 11.
8
Ibid., p. 10.
9
Ibid., p. 11.
10
Ibid., p. 397.
11
Ibid.
12
“The entire Turkish empire is ruled by one master, and all other men are his servants; he divided his
kingdom into sandjaks and dispatched various administrators to govern them, whom he transfers and changes
at his pleasure . . . They are slaves, bounden by him.” Il Principe e Discorsi, pp.26-7. Quoted from Anderson, p.
397.
13
Ibid., p. 398.
14
Islam was no doubt a subject of heated historical debates among many intellectuals in the seventeenth and
eighteenth –centuries. On the one hand, Humphrey Prideaux’s The True Nature of Imposture Revealed in the Life
of the Impostor Mohammad (1697) is a remarkable example of this derisive historiographic polemic. On the
other, a work like Henry Stubbe’s An Account of the Rise and Progress of Mahometanism with the Life of Mahomet
and a Vindication of Him and His Religion from the Calumnies of Christians (1676) expresses respect for Islam and
favorably likens it to elements in Christianity. In his book, Stubbe described Muḥammad as a “political
genius.” The difference of course is in circulation. Whereas Prideaux’s work circulated widely in Europe and
North America, Stubbe’s work remained unpublished. For more on the political turmoil and place of Islam in
constitutional debates in eighteenth-century Europe and America, see Denise A. Spellberg, “Could a Muslim
be President: An Eighteenth-Century Constitutional Debate,” Eighteenth-Century Studies vol. 39, no. 4 (2006):
485–506; see also Albert Hourani, “Islam and the Philosophers of History”: Middle Eastern Studies, Vol. 3, No. 3
(April, 1967), pp. 206-268.
15
See Siep Stuurman, “François Bernier and the Invention of Racial Classification”: History Workshop Journal,
No. 50 (Oxford UP, 2000), pp. 1-21.
21
16
Said, Culture and Imperialism (New York: Vintage Books, 1993), p. 240.
17
Anderson, p. 400.
Said, Orientalism, p. 119.
18
19
Theodor W. Adorno, History and Freedom: Lectures 1964-1965. Ed. Rolf Tiedemann, Trans. Rodney
Livingston (Malden: Polity Press.), p. 26.
20
Paul de Man, “Sign and Symbol in Hegel’s Aesthetics” (1964): Aesthetic Ideology (Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1996), p. 92.
21
Adorno, History and Freedom: Lectures 1964-1965, p. 65.
22
Among strong advocates of Hegelian accomplishment and domination is the French theorist Maurice
Blanchot who argues that in Hegel “philosophy comes together and accomplishes itself.” Maurice Blanchot,
The Infinite Conversation, trans. Susan Hanson (Minnesota: The University of Minnesota Press, 1993), p. 4; see
also Maurice Blanchot, The Step Not Beyond, trans. Lycette Nelson (New York: State University of New York
Press, 1992).
23
Despite the claim of many writers like Adorno, de Man, and Maurice Blanchot that there is no outside
Hegel, Marx attempts to position himself differently by critiquing Hegel for making the individual a property
of the state. Moreover, according to Marx, Hegel turned man into an abstract category. Marx, who saw
humans as concrete individuals forming social forces, believed that it was erroneous of Hegel to treat humans
as if they were a categorical type. However, Marx’s theory of ‘capital’ is impossible without the Hegelian
dialectic. To bridge this divide, the term ‘Hegelian Marxists’ emerged to address critics who benefit from both
streams, including Georg Lukács, Arthur Koestler, and Harold Laski. See Sidney Hook's From Hegel to Marx:
Studies in the Intellectual Development of Karl Marx (New York: Columbia UP, 1994); Herbert Marcuse, Hegel and the
Rise of Social Theory (Humanity Books, 1999); Alexandre Kojève's Introduction to the Reading of Hegel: Lectures on the
Phenomenology of the Spirit (Cornell: Cornell UP, 1980).
24
I mean by this term a theory that, instead of discarding its Others, employs them in order to further
distinguish itself (i.e. in opposition to them). Such theories thus work by utilizing their Others in the service of
self-definition. A prominent example of this type of theory is Augustine of Hippo’s explanation of why the
Jews had become dispersed on the earth and yet still survived. He wrote that the presence of Jews should serve
as a negative example to guide the Christians in their behavior: “it will be readily apparent to believing
Christians from the survival of the Jews, how those who killed the Lord when proudly empowered have
merited subjection.” Augustine, Contra Faustum, 12.12, pp. 341-42. Cited in Cohen, J. Living Letters of the Law.
Berkeley: University of California Press (1999), p. 29. I am grateful to Rachel Friedman for bringing this
reference to my attention.
25
Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, vol. 2, Determinate Religion, trans. R. F. Brown, P. C. Hodgson,
and J. M. Stewart, ed. Peter C. Hodgson (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987), p. 55. My italics.
26
Ibid., p. 158.
27
The German reads definition of den Fanatismus reads: “Begeisterung für ein Abstraktes, für einen abstrakten
Gedanken, der negierend sich zum Bestehenden verhält” (passion for an abstraction, for an abstract thought,
which relates as negating force to the existing object/thought). I am indebted to my colleague Volker
Langbehn for assisting me with this translation.
28
29
Ibid., p. 50.
See Martin Goodman, Mission and Conversion: Proselytizing in the Religious History of the Roman Empire (Oxford
UP, 1994) and Shaye Cohen The Beginnings of Jewishness (University of California Press, 2001).
30
Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, p. 156.
22
31
Hegel, Introduction to the Philosophy of History, trans. Leo Rauch (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company,
1988), p. 22.
32
Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy, trans. E.S. Haldane and Frances H. Simon Vol. I
(London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1892), pp. 118-19.
33
Jean-Luc Nancy, The Experience of Freedom, trans. Bridget McDonald (Stanford: Stanford UP, 1994), p. 20.
34
Ibid., p. 20.
35
See Adorno, History and Freedom: Lectures 1964-1965, pp. 5-9.
36
Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy, p. 34.
37
See Tsenay Serequeberhan, 1989. “The Idea of Colonialism in Hegel’s Philosophy of
Right”: International Philosophical Quarterly 39 (1989), pp. 301–318.
38
Hourani, “Islam and the Philosophers of History,” Middle Eastern Studies, Vol. 3, No. 3 (Apr., 1967), p. 246.
39
I borrow the term “continuist” from Gayatri Spivak, who employs it to critique Goux’s isomorphic analogy
of Freud, Lacan, and Marx in connection to the development of money-form and the psychological account of
the emergence of genital sexuality in his work Numismatiques. See Gayatri Spivak, “Scattered Speculations on
the Question of Value”: Diacritics, Vol. 15, No. 4, Marx after Derrida (Winter, 1985), pp. 73-93.
40
Jean-Joseph Goux, “Untimely Islam: September 11th and the Philosophies of History”: SubStance No. 115,
Vol. 37, no. 1, 2008), pp 54-55.
41
Ibid., p.56.
42
Ibid., p. 55.
43
Ibid., pp. 57-58.
44
Ibid., p. 58.
45
Hegel, Introduction to the Philosophy of History, p. 98.
46
Ibid., p. 98.
47
Ibid., p. 97.
48
Ibid., p. 98.
49
Ibid., p. 98.
50
Note that Hegel did the same thing with Christianity- dissociating it from the Crusades.
51
Goux, “Untimely Islam: September 11th and the Philosophies of History,” pp. 55-56.